<div style="float: left; border: 1px solid #d61810; margin: 1px;">
{{Infobox_Philosopher
{| cellspacing="0" style="width: 238px; background: #ffd600;"
| region = Western Philosophy
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #d61810; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id1-s|14}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Maryland state seal.png|40px|center|Seal of Maryland]]'''
| era = [[Ancient philosophy]]
| style="font-size: 8pt; color: #000000; padding: 4pt; line-height: 1.25em;" | <center> This user lives in the state of '''[[Maryland]]'''. <center/>
| color = #B0C4DE
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #000000; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id2-s|{{{id1-s|14}}}}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Flag of Maryland.svg|68px|center|Flag of Maryland]]'''
| image_name = §Platone (ca. 427-347 a.C.) - Monaco, Glyptotek - (foto mia, 24-01-2002) - 02.JPG
|}</div><br>
| image_caption = Plato - (ca. 427-347 B.C.)
| name = Plato
| birth = c.[[427 BC|427]]–[[428 BC]]
| death = [[347 BC]]
| school_tradition= [[Platonism]]
| main_interests = [[Metaphysics]], [[Epistemology]], [[Ethics]], [[Aesthetics]], [[Politics]], [[Education]], [[Philosophy of mathematics]], [[Metaphilosophy]]
| influences = [[Socrates]], [[Archytas]], [[Democritus]], [[Parmenides]], [[Pythagoras]], [[Homer]]
| influenced = Almost all Western [[philosopher]]s
| notable_ideas = [[Platonic realism]]
}}
{{otheruses}}
'''Plato''' ([[Greek language|ancient Greek]]: ''{{Polytonic|Πλάτων}}'', ''Plátōn'', "wide, broad-shouldered") (c. [[427 BC|427]]–c. [[347 BC]]), whose real name is believed to have been '''Aristocles''', was an immensely influential ancient [[Greeks|Greek]] [[philosopher]], writer of philosophical dialogues, and founder of the [[Academy]] in [[Athens]] where [[Aristotle]] studied. Plato is widely believed to have been a student of [[Socrates]] and to have been deeply influenced by his unjust execution.
{{Babel-2|en|en-us-n}}
The Platonic corpus is, like most collections of ancient literature, corrupt and disputed. His brilliance as a writer and thinker is proved in the core of his Socratic dialogues, but much of the material that is ascribed to him, including some dialogues, letters, and lawbooks is considered spurious. Plato is thought to have lectured at the Academy, although the pedagogical function of his dialogues, if any, is not known.
==Articles I created==
==Biography==
* [[Harry Vines]]
Plato is thought to have been born in Athens in May or December in [[428 BC|428]] or [[427 BC]] (like all the other ancient Greek philosophers, his birthdate is not exactly known). He was raised in a moderately well-to-do [[aristocratic]] family of four children. His father was named [[Ariston (Athenian)|Ariston]], and his mother [[Perictione]]. His family claimed descent from the ancient [[King of Athens|Athenian kings]], and he was related – though there is disagreement as to exactly how – to the prominent politician [[Critias]]. According to a late [[Hellenistic]] account by [[Diogenes Laertius]], Plato's given name was ''Aristocles'', whereas his [[wrestling]] coach, [[Ariston of Argos]], dubbed him "Platon", meaning "broad" on account of his robust figure. Diogenes mentions alternative accounts that Plato derived his name from the breadth (''platutês'') of his eloquence, or else because he was very wide (''platus'') across the forehead. According to [[Dicaearchus]], Plato wrestled at the [[Isthmian games]]. Such was his learning and ability that the ancient Greeks declared him to be the son of [[Apollo]] and told how, in his infancy, bees had settled on his lips, as prophecy of the honeyed words which were to flow from them.
* [[Naval Nuclear Power School]]
* [[North Pulaski High School]]
* [[Sylvan Hills High School]]
==Basics==
Plato may have traveled in [[Italy]], [[Sicily]], [[Egypt]], and [[Cyrene]]. Said to have returned to Athens at the age of forty, Plato founded one of the earliest known organized schools in Western civilization on a plot of land in the Grove of Academe. The [[Academy]] was "a large enclosure of ground which was once the property of a citizen at Athens named [[Academus]]... some, however, say that it received its name from an ancient hero" (Robinson, ''Arch. Graec.'' I i 16), and it operated until [[529|529 AD]], when it was closed by [[Justinian I]] of [[Byzantium]], who saw it as a threat to the propagation of [[Christianity]]. Many intellectuals were schooled in the Academy, the most prominent one being [[Aristotle]].
==Plato's Dialogues==
{|name="userboxes" id="userboxes" style="margin-left: 1em; margin-bottom: 0.5em; width: 242px; border: solid 0px; " align="top" colspan="3"
Plato's dialogues are a collection of conversations that Socrates has with a great variety of characters, young and old, obscure and well-known, foreign and Athenian. The dialogues often employ and refer to actual historical characters from the late fifth and early fourth centuries BC. Well known [[sophists]], political and military figures, businessmen and soothsayers, as well as writers and thinkers of every stripe - rhetors, poets, playwrights, speechmakers, and philosophers participate directly or indirectly in the dialogues. Next to [[Homer]]'s epic poems, Plato's dialogues are perhaps the single most important body of literature of Western classics.
{{User:UBX/male}}
{{user 1|black|white|[[Image:Mortarboard.jpg|40px]]| This user graduated from '''[[Sylvan Hills High School]]'''.}}
{{user 1|black|white|[[Image:Mortarboard.jpg|40px]]| This user graduated from '''[[Thomas Edison State College]]'''.}}
{{user Irish}}
{{User:UBX/Bicyclist}}
{{User:UBX/marathon}}
{{User:UBX/half-marathon}}
{{User:UBX/10K}}
{{User:UBX/5K}}
{{User singular they}}
{{User whichthat}}
{{User its}}
{{User its2}}
{{User french spacing}}
{{User NPS}}
<br>
==History==
Plato often depicts Socrates in intellectual combat with self-important men who over-sell their talents. The sophists Protagoras, Gorgias, and Hippias, for example, are depicted as know-it-alls in their namesake dialogues. Meno is a self-appointed moralist who owns a drove of slaves, Ion a rhapsodist as much in love with himself as with Homer, and Euthyphro a soothsayer who thinks that his own behavior is godlike. Socrates is as self-deprecating as his antagonists are boastful, yet he is no white knight. Plato often depicts him befriending young boys and making flirtatious remarks to anyone he finds handsome. While Socrates is apparently humble, he claims to be a spokesman for god, and despite his love of argument, makes many logical bloopers. He is often found defending outrageous claims that even he admits no one will accept.
<div style="float: left; border: 1px solid white; margin: 1px;">
Socrates is believed to have been an actual living personage, but how much of any given dialogue is historically accurate is heavily disputed. Socrates himself did not write anything, and no objective (non-literary) record of his life and/or philosophy exists. Besides Plato's dialogues, only two other sources of information about Socrates are extant, and these raise more questions than they resolve. The celebrated comic playwright [[Aristophanes]] refers disparagingly to Socrates in several dialogues, and in one play, ''[[The Clouds]]'', he is a lead character, a bamboozler-sophist who is head of an ancient think tank that teaches immoral logic. The third source is the works of [[Xenophon]], whose Socratic dialogues are not thought to provide insight into the [[Socratic problem]]: who was Socrates, what exactly did he teach and to whom, and what was his relation to Plato?
{| cellspacing="0" style="width: 238px; background: #ffd600;"
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: blue; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id1-s|14}}}pt;" | ''' '''
| style="font-size: 8pt; color: #100000; padding: 4pt; line-height: 1.25em;" | <center> This user once lived in the state of '''[[Pennsylvania]]'''. <center/>
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #000000; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id2-s|{{{id1-s|14}}}}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Flag of Pennsylvania.svg|68px|center|Flag of Pennsylvania]]'''
|}</div>
<div style="float: left; border: 1px solid white; margin: 1px;">
{| cellspacing="0" style="width: 238px; background: #ffd600;"
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: blue; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id1-s|14}}}pt;" | ''' '''
| style="font-size: 8pt; color: #100000; padding: 4pt; line-height: 1.25em;" | <center> This user twice lived in the state of '''[[Oklahoma]]'''. <center/>
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #000000; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id2-s|{{{id1-s|14}}}}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Flag of Oklahoma.svg|68px|center|Flag of Oklahoma]]'''
|}</div>
<div style="float: left; border: 1px solid white; margin: 1px;">
==Plato & Socrates==
{| cellspacing="0" style="width: 238px; background: #ffd600;"
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: blue; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id1-s|14}}}pt;" | ''' '''
| style="font-size: 8pt; color: #100000; padding: 4pt; line-height: 1.25em;" | <center> This user once lived in the state of '''[[Arkansas]]'''. <center/>
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #000000; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id2-s|{{{id1-s|14}}}}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Flag of Arkansas.svg|68px|center|Flag of Arkansas]]'''
|}</div>
<br>
<div style="float: left; border: 1px solid white; margin: 1px;">
{| cellspacing="0" style="width: 238px; background: #ffd600;"
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: blue; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id1-s|14}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Florida state seal.png|40px|center|Seal of Florida]]'''
| style="font-size: 8pt; color: #100000; padding: 4pt; line-height: 1.25em;" | <center> This user twice lived in the state of '''[[Florida]]'''. <center/>
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #000000; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id2-s|{{{id1-s|14}}}}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Flag of Florida.svg|68px|center|Flag of Florida]]'''
|}</div>
<div style="float: left; border: 1px solid white; margin: 1px;">
Plato hints that he was part of the Socratic entourage but never says so explicitly. In the ''[[Phaedo]]'' the title character lists those who were in attendance at the prison on Socrates' last day and says "Plato was ill" (''Phaedo'' 59b). In the ''[[Apology]]'', Plato distances himself from the inner circle. Socrates says there that the brothers of several of his former associates are in the audience. He says that Plato, brother to [[Adeimantus]], was present (''Apology'' 34a). Adeimantus appears in the ''[[Republic (Plato)|Republic]]'' as a disputant.
{| cellspacing="0" style="width: 238px; background: #ffd600;"
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: blue; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id1-s|14}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Illinois state seal.png|40px|center|Seal of Illinois]]'''
| style="font-size: 8pt; color: #100000; padding: 4pt; line-height: 1.25em;" | <center> This user twice lived in the state of '''[[Illinois]]'''. <center/>
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #000000; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id2-s|{{{id1-s|14}}}}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Flag of Illinois.svg|68px|center|Flag of Illinois]]'''
|}</div>
<div style="float: left; border: 1px solid white; margin: 1px;">
==Narration of the dialogues==
{| cellspacing="0" style="width: 238px; background: #ffd600;"
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: blue; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id1-s|14}}}pt;" | ''' '''
| style="font-size: 8pt; color: #100000; padding: 4pt; line-height: 1.25em;" | <center> This user once lived in the state of '''[[New York]]'''. <center/>
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #000000; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id2-s|{{{id1-s|14}}}}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Flag of New York.svg|68px|center|Flag of New York]]'''
|}</div>
<br>
<div style="float: left; border: 1px solid white; margin: 1px;">
{| cellspacing="0" style="width: 238px; background: #ffd600;"
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: blue; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id1-s|14}}}pt;" | ''' '''
| style="font-size: 8pt; color: #100000; padding: 4pt; line-height: 1.25em;" | <center> This user thrice lived in the state of '''[[Virginia]]'''. <center/>
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #000000; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id2-s|{{{id1-s|14}}}}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Flag of Virginia.svg|68px|center|Flag of Virginia]]'''
|}</div>
<div style="float: left; border: 1px solid white; margin: 1px;">
Plato never presents himself as a participant in any of the dialogues, and with the exception of the ''Apology'', he does not claim to have heard any of the dialogues firsthand. Some dialogs have no narrator (examples: [[Meno]], [[Gorgias]], [[Phaedrus (Plato)|Phaedrus]], [[Crito]], [[Euthyphro]]), some dialogs are narrated by Socrates, wherein he speaks in first person (examples: [[Lysis]], [[Charmides]], [[Apology (Plato)|Apology]], [[Republic (Plato)|Republic]]). In one dialog, [[Protagoras]], Socrates narrates to an unnamed friend a conversation he had previously with the sophist whose name gives title to the dialogue.
{| cellspacing="0" style="width: 238px; background: #ffd600;"
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: blue; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id1-s|14}}}pt;" | ''' '''
| style="font-size: 8pt; color: #100000; padding: 4pt; line-height: 1.25em;" | <center> This user once lived in the state of '''[[Ohio]]'''. <center/>
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #000000; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id2-s|{{{id1-s|14}}}}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Flag of Ohio.svg|68px|center|Flag of Ohio]]'''
|}</div>
<div style="float: left; border: 1px solid white; margin: 1px;">
Three dialogues, [[Phaedo]], [[Symposium]], and [[Theaetetus]], are narrated by disciples of Socrates, and all, apparently, from distant memories. Phaedo, an account of Socrates' final conversation and hemlock drinking, is narrated by Phaedo to Echecrates in a foreign city many years after the execution took place. The Symposium is narrated by by Apollodorus, a Socratic disciple, apparently to Glaucon. Apollodorus assures his listener that he is recounting the story, which took place when he himself was an infant, not to the best of his own memory, but to the best memory of Aristodemus, who told him the story years ago. In the ''[[Theaetetus]]'' (142c-143b), [[Euclid of Megara|Euclides]] says that he compiled the conversation from notes he took based on what Socrates told him of his conversation with the title character. With the exception of the Theaetetus, Plato gives no hint as to how these orally transmitted conversations came to be written down, least of all by himself.
{| cellspacing="0" style="width: 238px; background: #ffd600;"
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: blue; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id1-s|14}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Indiana state seal.png|40px|center|Seal of Indiana]]'''
| style="font-size: 8pt; color: #100000; padding: 4pt; line-height: 1.25em;" | <center> This user once lived in the state of '''[[Indiana]]'''. <center/>
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #000000; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id2-s|{{{id1-s|14}}}}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Flag of Indiana.svg|68px|center|Flag of Indiana]]'''
|}</div>
<br>
<div style="float: left; border: 1px solid white; margin: 1px;">
{| cellspacing="0" style="width: 238px; background: #ffd600;"
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: blue; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id1-s|14}}}pt;" | ''' '''
| style="font-size: 8pt; color: #100000; padding: 4pt; line-height: 1.25em;" | <center> This user once lived in the state of '''[[Michigan]]'''. <center/>
| style="width: 45px; height: 45px; background: #000000; text-align: center; font-size: {{{id2-s|{{{id1-s|14}}}}}}pt;" | '''[[Image:Flag of Michigan.svg|68px|center|Flag of Michigan]]'''
|}</div>
|-
Plato's absence from the dialogues is at odds with traditional belief that he was a disciple and part of the inner circle. The question of why Plato distances himself from three of his greatest dialogs explicitly by time, place, and authorship has never been satisfactorily answered.
|{{User:Disavian/Userboxes/United States}}
|-
|}
[[Category:Wikipedians in Maryland|Djharrity]]
Tradition tends to see Plato as writing a kind of "pseudo-history" of the life of Socrates, but the chronologies of the characters are inconsistent. For example, Alcibiades is a said to be a beardless young man in Protagoras, and Socrates is associating also with the son of Apollodorus, Hippocrates. In the Symposium, where Alcibiades is the older lover of Agathon, Apollodorus is a young man. Chronological discrepencies like this cannot be easily reconciled with the view that Plato is an historical writer in the modern sense.
[[Category:Wikipedians in the United States|Djharrity]]
Plato's dialogues bear at least some similarities to the classical plays, in having no more than three speakers "on stage" (speaking) at one time, and in often having "a chorus" of (silent) listeners.
{{ Userpage }}
==Trial of Socrates==
The trial of Socrates is the central, unifying event of the great Socratic dialogues. Because of this, Socrates' ''[[Apology (Plato)|Apology]]'' is perhaps the most often read of the dialogues. In the Apology, Socrates tries to dismiss rumors that he is a sophist and defends himself against charges of not believing in the gods and corruption of the young. Socrates insists that long-standing slander will be the real cause of his demise, and says the legal charges are essentially false. Socrates famously denies being wise, and explains how his life as a philosopher was launched by the oracle at Delphi. He says that his quest to resolve the riddle of the oracle put him at odds with his fellow man, and this is the reason he has been mistaken for a menace to the city-state of Athens.
The trial of Socrates is anomalous: from what is known about Athens in the fifth century BCE, it should not have taken place (see ''Gorgias'' 461e and ''Crito'' 45e). Atheism or similar charges were not a crime in free-speech Athens. It was not even unusual among intellectuals, nor condemned by the masses. The prize-winning plays of Aristophanes were not merely atheist, but made fun of the gods and their prophets and oracles. There is no record that Aristophanes was prosecuted for atheism, and some have speculated that comics enjoyed special immunities. However, there is no evidence of this. It is also puzzling that Socrates exonerates himself in large part by claiming to be sent on his philosophic mission by Apollo, an important figure in the standard Greek pantheon.
The charge of corruption of the young is harder to dismiss. Plato depicts Socrates as a flirt, and his romantic attentions are not confined to adults. One dialog in particular, the Charmides, pictures Socrates becoming aroused at the sight of a boy's private parts. The Apology gives no sense that the legal charges implied corruption of a sexual nature, and tradition interprets the corruption as moral/intellectual in nature. Socrates says in the Apology that he has merely advised the young men who are slanderously termed his disciples that they should care more about virtue than their careers, public service, or families. Attention to such things was the mark of virtue in ancient Athens. This "moral misunderstanding" has captivated history ever since Plato told the story.
==Unity & Diversity of the dialogues==
If Plato's important dialogues do not refer to the execution explicitly, they allude to it, or use characters or themes that play a part in it. Five dialogues foreshadow the trial: In the ''[[Theaetetus]]'' (210d) and the ''[[Euthyphro]]'' (2a–b) Socrates tells people that he is about to face corruption charges. In ''[[Meno]]'' (94e-95a), one of the men who brings legal charges against Socrates, [[Anytus]], warns him about the trouble he may get into if he does not stop criticizing important people. In the ''[[Gorgias]]'', Socrates says that his trial will be like a doctor prosecuted by a cook who asks a jury of children to choose between the doctor's bitter medicine and the cook's tasty treats (521e–522a). In the ''[[Republic]]'' (7.517e), Socrates explains why an enlightened man (presumably himself) will stumble in a courtroom situation. The ''Apology'' is Socrates' defense speech, and the ''[[Crito]]'' and ''[[Phaedo]]'' take place in prison after the conviction. In the ''[[Protagoras]]'', Socrates is a guest at the home of [[Callias III|Callias]], son of [[Hipponicus]], a man whom Socrates disparages in the ''Apology'' as having wasted a great amount of money on sophists' fees.
Two other important dialogues, the ''[[Symposium (Plato)|Symposium]]'' and the ''[[Phaedrus (Plato)|Phaedrus]]'', are linked to the main storyline by characters. In the ''Apology'' (19b, c), Socrates says [[Aristophanes]] slandered him in a comic play, and blames him for causing his bad reputation, and ultimately, his death. In the ''Symposium'', the two of them are drinking together with other friends. The character Phaedrus is linked to the main story line by character (Phaedrus is also a participant in the ''Symposium'' and the ''Protagoras'') and by theme (the philosopher as divine emissary, etc.) The Protagoras is also strongly linked to the ''Symposium'' by characters: all of the formal speakers at the ''Symposium'' (with the exception of Aristophanes) are present at the home of Callias in that dialogue. [[Charmides]] and his guardian [[Critias]] are present for the discussion in the ''Protagoras''. Examples of characters crossing between dialogues can be further multiplied. The ''Protagoras'' contains the largest gathering of Socratic associates.
In the dialogues for which Plato is most celebrated and admired, Socrates is concerned with human and political virtue, has a distinctive personality, and friends and enemies who "travel" with him from dialogue to dialogue. This is not to say that Socrates is consistent: he not only appears to contradict himself from dialog to dialog, he often appears to contradict himself within a single dialog.
Many other dialogues ascribed to Plato also use the Socratic character, but do not share this pronounced concern for virtue. In these dialogues, Plato uses Socrates as a mere name, a voice-marker who does not have the distinctive, self-depricating wit of the important dialogues. The metaphysical dialogues attributed to Plato do not contain material of human interest, but are very abstract and read by specialists.
The dialogues have been divided by influential scholarship into the early, middle and late periods. The late Princeton scholar and classist, [[Gregory Vlastos]] argued that the ''Euthyphro'', ''Apology'', ''Crito'' and ''Phaedo'' were written first and are a more or less historical record of the philosophy of the historical character Socrates. Vlastos argues that Plato's early dialogues represent Socratic philosophy, and that the middle and later dialogues can be counted on to give the reader Plato's own philosophy.{{fact}} This division of the dialogues is not indicated by the dialogues themselves.
==The question of Socratic literacy==
Tradition has long puzzled over why Socrates did not leave a written legacy. The ancient Greeks had been highly literate for several hundred years before the [[Golden Age]] of Greece. Entire works and fragments remain from dozens of poets, philosophers, scientists, and rhetoricians. Socrates left not even a single line, and in only one dialogue indicates that he has ever personally put pen to paper. In [[Phaedo]], Socrates tells his disciples that he has spent his last days in prison writing songs using material from [[Aesop's fables]]. Aesop's fables are little satires which employ animal characters and represent the low-end of Greek literature.
Plato hints that Socrates may have been only semi-literate.{{fact}} In the ''[[Phaedo]]'', Socrates is reported to have said that he got his idea that mind is the cause of everything from a man who was reading a book out loud. He said the man told him the author was [[Anaxagoras]] (''Phaedo'' 97c). This suggests that Socrates was not in a position to personally verify, but the reader is not told precisely why. In the ''Apology'', Socrates seems to reject the wisdom of Anaxagoras, saying that his silly (atheist) ideas about the sun being a stone and the earth being a mass of earth, and not gods, can be purchased in the market for a drachma (''Apology'' 26d,e).
Socrates is similarly (apparently) inconsistent in his attitude towards Homer, the most revered writer in classical Greece. He famously recommends in the ''Republic'' that favorites like [[Homer]]'s ''[[Iliad]]'' and ''[[Odyssey]]'' be rewritten, and Homer be sent into exile (''Repub.'' 3.398a,b). He avers here and later in the dialog that the more poetic and lovely writing is, the worse is its effect upon the soul. Socrates believes that the best literature gives unambiguous praise to good men, and criticism to bad men, and that anything else is confusing.
In the ''[[Phaedrus]]'' Socrates criticizes the innovation of writing because it implants forgetfulness in the soul of the reader and because writing so often gets into the hands of people who have no business with it (275a-e). This critical attitude towards literature comes from Socrates, whose ideas cannot be simply conflated with Plato's personal ideology. Plato's mastery of Greek is unquestionable: the grammatical and rhetorical structures of the dialogues are extremely complex; the arguments and analogies, stories and fables, and allusions and allegories are unmatched in cleverness; the wealth of his themes has no parallel, ancient or modern.
==His Work==
[[Image:Plato-raphael.jpg|thumb|left|[[Raphael]]'s Plato in ''[[The School of Athens]]'' fresco, probably in the likeness of [[Leonardo da Vinci]]. Plato gestures to the heavens, representing his belief in [[The Forms]].]]
==Structure==
Some of Plato's dialogues are framed by human elements. The clearest example of this is [[Phaedo]], wherein Socrates dismisses his wife [[Xanthippe]] from the prison at the beginning of the dialog, and again towards the end. The frame elements suggest that Socrates' relationship with his disciples, who mourn the loss of their spiritual "father" is more important to him than his biological family. In this dialogue, an entire chorus of people is said to be silently listening to a very long conversation, and apparently, saying nothing.
Other dialogues, such as [[Euthyphro]] and [[Crito]], involve only two characters who are not said to be overheard by anyone else. The characters are meant to be compared and contrasted. Socrates is more like Euthyphro (whom he mocks) than he thinks. Both are pious men whose knowledge of god's will comes from different sources - Euthyphro reads myths and takes them literally, while Socrates relies on divine voices in his head). Socrates is less compatible with his friend Crito than he thinks, and even says that people who are so morally at odds ought to despise each other. Sometimes characters pop in and out of a dialogue, as a slave and an aristocrat ([[Anytus]]) in the [[Meno]].
Two of Plato's dialogues are better described as monologues. The often-read [[Apology]] is as brilliant a speech as the little-read [[Menexenus]] is hackneyed. Other dialogs also seem to be literary twins: [[Gorgias]] and [[Protagoras]] depict Socrates being invited to converse with a well-known rhetorician who is visiting Athens. Lysis and Charmides both picture Socrates chatting with boys who are young enough to be attended by guardians. Phaedrus and Symposium are a pair of dialogues linked by the theme of man-boy love.
==Analogies, Arguments & Themes==
The analogies in the dialogues are as interesting as the arguments, but less often noted. Socrates frequently compares ideas with children, and always disfavorably (''Symposium'' 209a–e). He also compares them with food (''Protag'' 313c–314c). Socrates repeatedly compares the philosopher, who cures the mind (''psyche'') of its worst ailment, ignorance, with a medical doctor (''iatros''). Today, doctors of the mind are called "psych-iatrists". Socrates compared the body to a prison house for the soul, and promoted the distinction that remains today, that body and soul are hard to reconcile. Socrates also famously compares himself to a midwife to men and boys who are "pregnant with thought."
In several dialogs, Socrates compares intellectual debate to the physical contests so popular in the ancient Greek world. In the ''Gorgias'' he says that trainers cannot be blamed for the misbehaviors of their students. He says that you would not exile his trainer if a boxing student started punching out his friends and parents, and just so, a teacher of rhetoric cannot be blamed if his students use their skills for unjust purposes. In the ''Lesser Hippias'', Socrates says that a person who lies deliberately is a better man than the man who lies unwittingly, just as a man who throws an athletic contest is better than the man who loses from lack of skill.
The debates in the great Socratic dialogues concern above all, human and political virtue. Very much on Plato's mind is the question of whether a father has much to do with how well his sons turn out. Socrates mocks fathers who spent exhorbitant fees on tutors and trainers for their sons, and doubts whether "virtue" is transmissible at all. Socrates repeatedly ventures the idea that good character is a gift from god. Under the rubric of human virtue fall the debates about piety, self-restraint, courage, friendship and love.
In several dialogs, Socrates floats the idea that [[Knowledge]] is a matter of recollection, and not of learning, observation, or study. Socrates is often found arguing that knowledge is not empirical, and that it comes from divine insight. Dialogs contrast knowledge and opinion, perception and [[reality]], [[nature]] and custom, body and soul, pleasure and pain, crime and punishment. Socrates is generally consistent in believing in the immortality of the soul, and several dialogs end with Socrates' imaginings of the [[afterlife]]. Several dialogues tackle questions about the function of art and the interpretation literature. The dialog ''Ion'' suggests that Homer's Iliad functioned in the ancient greek world much as the bible does today in the modern Christian world: as divinely inspired writing that contains moral guidance if properly interpreted.
On politics and art, religion and science, justice and medicine, virtue and vice, rhetoric and rhapsody, human nature and sexuality, love and wisdom, Socrates and his company of disputants had something to say. Plato's insights are as rich as they are timeless, and yet not always easy to discern.
==Socrates and the female==
In two dialogues, the ''[[Menexenus]]'' and the ''[[Symposium]]'', Socrates claims to have been tutored by a woman. In the ''Menexenus'', Socrates says that he was a student of [[Aspasia]], the mistress of [[Pericles]], who taught him the art of rhetoric, and that the earth is the "true mother" of men. Women who give birth, she taught him, only imitate the earth, in whose bosom dead soldiers comfortably rest. The ''Menexenus'' is thought to mock the Athenian custom of giving a [[Funeral oration (ancient Greece)|funeral oration]] for soldiers who had died in battle. Aspasia's speech pretends that the land of Athens gives life to its citizens/soldiers/sons, and that they "belong" to the land rather than to their human parents.
In the ''[[Symposium]]'', Socrates tells a company of his friends that he learned everything he knows about love from the sorceress [[Diotima]]. Diotima taught him that ideas, which are the offspring of the intellectual intercourse between men and boys, are superior to the offspring of the bodies of women. Socrates says that he learned that men who are sexually attracted to women are misguided, searching for immortality through children. Ideas, she told him, are more likely to make a man famous.
In the ''[[Apology]]'' Socrates seems to subscribe to standard sexist stereotypes when he tells the jury that he will not weep and wail before the jury and beg for mercy because men who use such tactics for acquittal are "no better than women". In the ''[[Republic]]'', Socrates does a complete filp flop, and appears to be not just liberal, but a radical feminist. He argues that gender is irrelevant to aptitude for the professions and declares that women ought to be educated along with the men, and in particular, be trained in combat. Socrates says that in his ideal world, women will perform their military exercises naked alongside the men. When his partner in conversation objects that foreigners will laugh, Socrates says that it is no matter, because the women will be "clad in virtue."
Socrates also abolishes the nuclear family in his design of a more perfect city than Athens. He says that women will will be held in common, and be bred like hounds. The bravest warriors will have maximum access to women. Besides rewarding battle courage, the system will produce a better class of warriors in time. This suggestion has a parallel in Aristophanes' play, "[[Women at the Assembly]]", where women themselves rewrite the laws of Athens and abolish the private household.
==Metaphysics==
{{main|Platonic realism}}
[[Image:Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg|thumb|right|200px|Detail of [[The School of Athens]] by [[Raffaello Sanzio]], 1509, showing Plato (pointing upwards, as if to the Form of the Good) and [[Aristotle]] (holding his hand palm down to Earth, favouring material evidence).]]
Platonism has traditionally been interpreted as a form of metaphysical [[dualism]] {{fact}}, sometimes referred to as Platonic realism, and is regarded as one of the earlier representatives of metaphysical [[objective idealism]].<ref>[http://www.philosophos.com/knowledge_base/archives_12/philosophy_questions_12.html]</ref> According to this reading, Plato's metaphysics divides the world into two distinct aspects: the intelligible world of "forms", and the perceptual world we see around us. The perceptual world consists of imperfect copies of the intelligible forms or [[idea]]s. These forms are unchangeable and perfect, and are only comprehensible by the use of the intellect or understanding, that is, a capacity of the mind that does not include [[perception|sense-perception]] or [[imagination]].
In the ''Republic'' Books VI and VII, Plato uses a number of [[metaphor]]s to explain his metaphysical views: the [[Plato's metaphor of the sun|metaphor of the sun]], the well-known [[Plato's allegory of the cave|allegory of the cave]], and most explicitly, [[the divided line of Plato|the divided line]].
Taken together, these metaphors convey a complex, and, in places, difficult theory: there is something called [[The Form of the Good]] or Idea of the Good (often interpreted as Plato's god), which is the ultimate object of [[knowledge]] and which, as it were, sheds light on all the other forms (i.e., [[universal (metaphysics)|universals]]: [[abstraction|abstract]] [[kind (word)|kinds]] and [[attribute]]s), and from which all other forms "emanate". The Form of the Good does this in somewhat the same way as the sun sheds light on, or makes visible and "generates" things, in the perceptual world.
In the perceptual world, the particular objects we see around us bear only a dim resemblance to the more ultimately real forms of Plato's intelligible world; it is as if we are seeing shadows of cut-out shapes on the walls of a cave, which are mere representations of the [[reality]] outside the cave, illuminated by the sun.
We can imagine everything in the [[universe]] represented on a line of increasing reality; it is divided once unevenly, and then once again in each of the resulting parts in the same ratio as the first division (Regardless of the ratio, the two middle sections of the line are equal). The first division represents that between the intelligible and the perceptual worlds. This is followed by a corresponding division in each of these worlds: the segment representing the perceptual world is divided into segments representing "real things" on the one hand, and shadows, reflections, and representations of those things on the other. Similarly, the segment representing the intelligible world is divided into segments representing [[first principle]]s and most general forms, on the one hand, and more derivative, "reflected" forms, on the other. (See [[the divided line of Plato]])
Plato's metaphysics, and particularly its [[dualism]] between the intelligible and the perceptual, would inspire later [[Neoplatonism|Neoplatonist]] thinkers, such as [[Plotinus]] and [[Gnosticism|Gnostics]], and many other metaphysical realists. Although Platonist philosophers like Plotinus rejected Gnosticism (see Plotinus' ''[[Enneads]]''). One reason being the Gnostic vilification of nature and Plato's [[demiurge]] from ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]''. Plato also influenced [[Saint Justin Martyr]]. For more on Platonic realism in general, see [[Platonic realism]] and [[the Forms]].
Although this interpretation of Plato's writings (particularly the ''Republic'') has enjoyed immense popularity throughout the long history of Western philosophy, it is also possible to interpret his suggestions more conservatively, favoring a more [[Epistemology | epistemological]] than metaphysical reading of such famous metaphors as the Cave and the Divided Line. There are obvious parallels between the Cave allegory and the life of Plato's teacher [[Socrates]] (who was killed in his attempt to "open the eyes" of the Athenians). This example reveals the dramatic complexity that often lies under the surface of Plato's writing (remember that in the ''Republic'', it is Socrates who relates the story).
== Theory of Forms ==
{{main | Theory of Forms }}
Plato's Theory of Forms indicates that the sensory world that is the reality, which we as human beings experience, is only a shadow of a higher realm. In this higher realm, Plato assures us that there exist the Forms that embody the true nature of the pale shadows. What we know as sweet is only an afterimage of the Form of Sweetness. The luminous brightness of the sun is only a corporeal display of the Form of Brightness.
The Forms should be understood as a unity amidst disparate things. The disparate things are the things of the sense world, the forms are our intellectual apprehension of the true meaning of those things; and even the lifeblood of the empirical things themselves. The Forms are static, perfect and unchanging: necessary characteristics if they are going to be used to makes sense of the empirical world. Following this logic, then, Plato infers a unity to the forms themselves that could be considered the Ultimate Form, or the Form of Form. This is one quality which all Forms share. Later Christian thinkers influenced by [[Neoplatonism|Neo-Platonists]] would identify this Ultimate Form with God; though certainly famous pagan [[Neoplatonism|Neo-Platonists]] such as [[Plotinus]] would do the same.
== Epistemology ==
{{main | Platonic epistemology}}
Plato also had some influential opinions on the nature of [[knowledge]] and [[learning]] which he propounded in the ''[[Meno (Plato)|Meno]]'', which began with the question of whether [[virtue]] can be taught, and proceeded to expound the concepts of [[recollection]], learning as the discovery of pre-existing knowledge, and [[right opinion]], opinions which are correct but have no clear justification.
Also, many have interpreted Plato as stating that [[knowledge]] is [[justified true belief]], an influential view which informed future developments in modern analytic epistemology. This interpretation is based on a reading of the ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]'' wherein Plato argues that belief is to be distinguished from knowledge on account of justification. Many years later, [[Edmund Gettier]] famously demonstrated the problems of the justified true belief account of knowledge. This interpretation, however, imports modern analytic and empiricist categories onto Plato himself and is better read on its own terms than as Plato's view.
Really, In the ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]'', ''[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]'', ''[[Republic (dialogue)|Republic]]'', and the ''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]'' Plato himself associates knowledge with the apprehension of unchanging Forms and their relationships to one another (which he calls "expertise" in [[Dialectic]]). More explicitly, Plato himself argues in the ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus ]]'' that knowledge is always proportionate to the realm from which it is gained. In other words, if one derives their account of something experientially, because the world of sense is in flux, the views therein attained will be mere opinions. And opinions are characterized by a lack of necessity and stability. On the other hand, if one derives their account of something by way of the non-sensible forms, because these forms are unchanging, so too is the account derived from them. It is only in this sense that Plato uses the term "[[knowledge]]."
== The state ==
Plato's philosophical views had many societal implications, especially on the idea of an ideal [[state]] or government. There is some discrepancy between his early and later views. Some of the most famous doctrines are contained in the ''Republic'' during his middle period, as well as in the ''[[Laws (dialogue)|Laws]]'' and the ''[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]''. However, because Plato wrote dialogues, it is assumed that Socrates is often speaking for Plato. This assumption may not be true in all cases.
Plato, through the words of Socrates, asserts that societies have a tripartite class structure corresponding to the appetite/spirit/reason structure of the individual soul.
* ''Productive'' (Workers) — the labourers, carpenters, plumbers, masons, merchants, farmers, ranchers, etc. These correspond to the "appetite" part of the soul.
* ''Protective'' (Warriors or Auxiliaries) — those who are adventurous, strong and brave; in the armed forces. These correspond to the "spirit" part of the soul.
* ''Governing'' (Rulers or Guardians) — those who are intelligent, rational, self-controlled, in love with wisdom, well suited to make decisions for the community. These correspond to the "reason" part of the soul and are very few.
According to this model, the principles of [[Athenian democracy]] (as it existed in his day) are rejected as only a few are fit to rule. Instead of rhetoric and persuasion, Plato says reason and wisdom should govern. This does not equate to [[tyranny]], [[despotism]], or [[oligarchy]], however. As Plato puts it:
: "Until philosophers rule as kings or those who are now called kings and leading men genuinely and adequately philosophise, that is, until political power and philosophy entirely coincide, while the many natures who at present pursue either one exclusively are forcibly prevented from doing so, cities will have no rest from evils,... nor, I think, will the human race." (''Republic'' 473c-d)
Plato describes these "philosopher kings" as "those who love the sight of truth" (''Republic'' 475c) and supports the idea with the analogy of a captain and his ship or a doctor and his medicine. Sailing and health are not things that everyone is qualified to practice by nature. A large part of the ''Republic'' then addresses how the educational system should be set up to produce these philosopher kings.
However, it must be taken into account that the ideal city outlined in the ''Republic'' is qualified by Socrates as the ideal ''luxurious'' city, examined to determine how it is that injustice and justice grow in a city (''Republic'' 372e). According to Socrates, the "true" and "healthy" city is instead the one first outlined in book II of the ''Republic'', 369c–372d, containing farmers, craftsmen, merchants, and wage-earners, but lacking the guardian class of philosopher-kings as well as delicacies such as "perfumed oils, incense, prostitutes, and pastries", in addition to paintings, gold, ivory, couches, a multitude of occupations such as poets and hunters, and war.
In addition, the ideal city is used as an image to illuminate the state of one's soul, or the [[will]], [[reason]], and [[desire]]s combined in the human body. Socrates is attempting to make an image of a rightly ordered human, and then later goes on to describe the different kinds of humans that can be observed, from tyrants to lovers of money in various kinds of cities. The ideal city is not promoted, but only used to magnify the different kinds of individual humans and the state of their soul. However, the [[philosopher king]] image was used by many after Plato to justify their personal political beliefs. The philosophic soul according to Socrates has reason, will, and desires united in virtuous harmony. A philosopher has the [[moderate]] love for [[wisdom]] and the [[courage]] to act according to wisdom. Wisdom is [[knowledge]] about the [[Goodness and value theory|Good]] or the right relations between all that [[exist]]s.
Wherein it concerns states and rulers, Plato has made interesting arguments. For instance he asks which is better - a bad democracy or a country reigned by a tyrant. He argues that it is better to be ruled by a bad tyrant (since then there is only one person committing bad deeds) than be a bad democracy (since here all the people are now responsible for such actions.)
According to Socrates a state, which is made up of different kinds of souls, will overall decline from an [[aristocracy]] to a [[timocracy]], then to an [[oligarchy]], then to a [[democracy]], and finally to [[tyranny]]. Perhaps Plato is trying to warn us of the various kinds of immoderate souls that can rule over a state, and what kind of wise souls are best to advise and give counsel to the rulers that are often lovers of [[Political power|power]], money, fame, and popularity.
== Platonic scholarship ==
[[Image:Plato.png|thumb|"The safest general characterisation of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato." ([[Alfred North Whitehead]], ''[[Process and Reality]]'', 1929).]]
Plato's thought is often compared with that of his most famous student, [[Aristotle]], whose reputation during the Western [[Middle Ages]] so completely eclipsed that of Plato that the [[Scholasticism|Scholastic]] philosophers referred to Aristotle as "the Philosopher". However, in the [[Byzantine Empire]], the study of Plato continued.
The Medieval scholastic philosophers did not have access to the works of Plato, nor the knowledge of [[Greek language|Greek]] needed to read them. Plato's original writings were essentially lost to Western civilization until they were brought from [[Constantinople]] in the century before its fall, by [[George Gemistos Plethon]]. Medieval scholars knew of Plato only through translations into [[Latin]] from the translations into [[Arabic language|Arabic]] by [[Iran|Persian]] and Arab scholars. These scholars not only translated the texts of the ancients, but expanded them by writing extensive [[Close reading|commentaries]] and [[interpretation]]s on Plato's and [[Aristotle]]'s works (see [[Al-Farabi]], [[Avicenna]], [[Averroes]]).
Only in the [[Renaissance]], with the general resurgence of interest in classical civilization, did knowledge of Plato's philosophy become widespread again in the West. Many of the greatest early modern scientists and artists who broke with [[Scholasticism]] and fostered the flowering of the Renaissance, with the support of the Plato-inspired [[Lorenzo de Medici]], saw Plato's philosophy as the basis for progress in the arts and sciences. By the [[19th century]], Plato's reputation was restored, and at least on par with Aristotle's.
Notable Western philosophers have continued to draw upon Plato's work since that time. Plato's influence has been especially strong in mathematics and the sciences. It inspired the greatest advances in logic since Aristotle, due to [[Gottlob Frege]] and his followers [[Kurt Gödel]], [[Alonzo Church]], and [[Alfred Tarski]], the last of whom summarised his approach by reversing Aristotle's famous declaration of sedition from the ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' (1096a15: ''Amicus Plato sed magis amica veritas''): ''Inimicus Plato sed magis amica veritas'' ("Plato is a friend, but truth is yet a greater friend"). [[Albert Einstein]] drew on Plato's understanding of an immutable reality that underlies the flux of appearances for his objections to the probabilistic picture of the physical universe propounded by [[Niels Bohr]] in his interpretation of [[quantum mechanics]]. Conversely, thinkers that diverged from [[ontology|ontological]] models and [[moral]] ideals in their own philosophy, have tended to disparage Platonism from more or less informed perspectives. Thus [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] attacked Plato's moral and political theories, [[Martin Heidegger]] argued against Plato's alleged obfuscation of ''[[Being]]'', and [[Karl Popper]] argued in ''[[The Open Society and Its Enemies]]'' (1945) that Plato's alleged proposal for a government system in the ''Republic'' was prototypically [[totalitarianism|totalitarian]]. [[Leo Strauss]] is considered by some as the prime thinker involved in the recovery of Platonic thought in its more political, and less metaphysical, form. Deeply influenced by Nietzsche and Heidegger, Strauss nonetheless rejects their condemnation of Plato and looks to the dialogues for a solution to what all three thinkers acknowledge as 'the crisis of the West.'
== Bibliography ==
Plato's writings (most of them [[dialogue]]s) have been published in several fashions; this has led to several conventions regarding the naming and referencing of Plato's texts.
Those works ascribed to Plato that have a separate Wikipedia article can be found in [[:Category:Dialogues of Plato]]
=== Tetralogy ===
One tradition regarding the arrangement of Plato's texts is according to [[tetralogy|tetralogies]]. This scheme is ascribed by [[Diogenes Laertius]] to an ancient scholar and court astrologer to [[Tiberius]] named [[Thrasyllus]].
In the list below, works by Plato are marked (1) if there is no consensus among scholars as to whether Plato is the author, and (2) if scholars generally agree that Plato is ''not'' the author of the work. Unmarked works are assumed to have been written by Plato.
==== Tetralogies ====
* I. ''[[Euthyphro]]'', ''[[Apology (Plato)|(The) Apology (of Socrates)]]'', ''[[Crito]]'', ''[[Phaedo]]''
* II. ''[[Cratylus (dialogue)|Cratylus]]'', ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]'', ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]'', ''[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]''
* III. ''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]'', ''[[Philebus]]'', ''[[Symposium (Plato dialogue)|(The) Symposium]]'', ''[[Phaedrus (dialogue)|Phaedrus]]''
* IV. ''[[First Alcibiades]]'' (1), ''[[Second Alcibiades]]'' (2), ''[[Hipparchus (dialogue)|Hipparchus]]'' (2), ''[[Rival Lovers|(The) (Rival) Lovers]]'' (2)
* V. ''[[Theages]]'' (2), ''[[Charmides (dialogue)|Charmides]]'', ''[[Laches (dialogue)|Laches]]'', ''[[Lysis (dialogue)|Lysis]]''
* VI. ''[[Euthydemus (dialogue)|Euthydemus]]'', ''[[Protagoras (dialogue)|Protagoras]]'', ''[[Gorgias (dialogue)|Gorgias]]'', ''[[Meno]]''
* VII. ''[[Hippias major|(Greater) Hippias (major)]]'' (1), ''[[Hippias minor|(Lesser) Hippias (minor)]]'', ''[[Ion (dialogue)|Ion]]'', ''[[Menexenus]]''
* VIII. ''[[Clitophon]]'' (1), ''[[Republic (dialogue)|(The) Republic]]'', ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]'', ''[[Critias (dialogue)|Critias]]''
* IX. ''[[Minos (dialogue)|Minos]]'' (2), ''[[Laws (dialogue)|(The) Laws]]'', ''[[Epinomis]]'' (2), ''[[Seventh Letter]]'' (1).
==== Works not in Thrasyllus' tetralogies ====
The remaining works were transmitted under Plato's name, most of them already considered spurious in antiquity, and so were not included by Thrasyllus in his tetralogical arrangement. These works are labelled as ''Notheuomenoi'' ("spurious") or ''Apocrypha''.
* ''[[Axiochus]]'' (2), ''[[Definitions (Plato)|Definitions]]'' (2), ''[[Demodocus (dialogue)|Demodocus]]'' (2), ''[[Epigrams (Plato)|Epigrams]]'', ''[[Eryxias]]'' (2), ''[[Halcyon (dialogue)|Halcyon]]'' (2), ''[[On Justice]]'' (2), ''[[On Virtue]]'' (2), ''[[Sisyphus (dialogue)|Sisyphus]]'' (2).
=== Stephanus pagination ===
The usual system for making unique references to sections of the text by Plato derives from a [[16th century]] edition of Plato's works by [[Henri Estienne|Henricus Stephanus]]. An overview of Plato's writings according to this system can be found in the [[Stephanus pagination]] article.
=== Chronology ===
The exact order in which Plato's dialogues were written is not known, nor is the extent to which some might have been later revised and rewritten. However, according to modern [[linguistics|linguistic theory]] there is enough information internal to the dialogues to form a rough chronology. The dialogues are normally grouped into three fairly distinct periods, with a few of them considered transitional works, and some just difficult to place. [[Friedrich Schleiermacher]], whose translation of Plato into German still stands uncontested in Germany, is very likely the first to have divided Plato's dialogues into three distinct periods. However, his ordering is quite different from the modern one, and rather than being based upon philology, he claims to have traced Plato's philosophical development. Schleiermacher divides the dialogues thus:
# Foundation: ''[[Phaedrus (dialogue)|Phaedrus]]'', ''[[Lysis]]'', ''[[Protagoras (dialogue)|Protagoras]]'', ''[[Laches (dialogue)|Laches]]'', ''[[Charmides (dialogue)|Charmides]]'', ''[[Euthyphro]]'', ''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]'';
# Transition: ''[[Gorgias (dialogue)|Gorgias]]'', ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]'', ''[[Meno (Plato)|Meno]]'', ''[[Euthydemus (dialogue)|Euthydemus]]'', ''[[Cratylus (dialogue)|Cratylus]]'', ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]'', ''[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]'', ''[[Symposium]]'', ''[[Phaedo]]'', ''[[Philebus]]''
# Culmination: ''[[The Republic (dialogue)|The Republic]]'', ''(Critias, Timaeus, The Laws)''
The final three dialogues above, in parentheses, were not translated by Schleiermacher, though ten other dialogues (including ''[[Ion]]'', etc.) were translated and deemed spurious. Finally, Schleiermacher maintained that the ''[[Apology (Plato)|Apology]]'' and probably the ''[[Crito]]'' were Plato's memory of Socrates' actual words.
[[Lewis Campbell]] was the first to make exhaustive use of [[stylometry]] to prove objectively that the ''Critias'', ''Timaeus'', ''Laws'', ''Philebus'', ''Sophist'', and ''Statesman'' were all clustered together as a group, while the ''Parmenides'', ''Phaedrus'', ''Republic'', and ''Theaetetus'' belong to a separate group, which must be earlier (given [[Aristotle]]'s statement in his ''Politics''<ref>[http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.01.0058&layout=&loc=2.1264b 1264b24-27]</ref> that the ''Laws'' was written after the ''Republic''; cf. [[Diogenes Laertius]] ''Lives'' 3.37).
Many of the positions in the ordering are still highly disputed. The generally agreed upon modern ordering is as follows.
==== Early dialogues ====
Socrates figures in all of these, and they are considered the most faithful representations of the historical Socrates; hence they are also called the [[Socratic dialogues]]. Most of them consist of Socrates discussing a subject, often an ethical one (friendship, piety) with a friend or with someone presumed to be an expert on it. Through a series of questions he will show that apparently they don't understand it at all. It is left to the reader to figure out if "he" really understands "it". This makes these dialogues "indirect" teachings. This period also includes several pieces surrounding the trial and execution of Socrates.
* ''[[Apology (Plato)|Apology]]''
* ''[[Crito]]''
* ''[[Charmides (dialogue)|Charmides]]''
* ''[[Laches (dialogue)|Laches]]''
* ''[[Lysis (dialogue)|Lysis]]''
* ''[[Euthyphro]]''
* ''[[Menexenus]]''
* ''[[Lesser Hippias]]''
* ''[[Ion (dialogue)|Ion]]''
The following are variously considered transitional or middle period dialogues:
* ''[[Gorgias (dialogue)|Gorgias]]''
* ''[[Protagoras (dialogue)|Protagoras]]''
* ''[[Meno]]''
==== Middle dialogues ====
Late in the early dialogues Plato's Socrates actually begins supplying answers to some of the questions he asks, or putting forth positive doctrines. This is generally seen as the first appearance of Plato's own views. The first of these, that goodness is wisdom and that no one does evil willingly, was perhaps Socrates' own view. What becomes most prominent in the middle dialogues is the idea that knowledge comes of grasping unchanging forms or essences, paired with the attempts to investigate such essences. The immortality of the soul, and specific doctrines about justice, truth, and beauty, begin appearing here. The [[Symposium (Plato dialogue)|Symposium]] and the [[Republic (dialogue)|Republic]] are considered the centrepieces of Plato's middle period.
* ''[[Euthydemus (dialogue)|Euthydemus]]''
* ''[[Cratylus (dialogue)|Cratylus]]''
* ''[[Phaedo]]''
* ''[[Phaedrus (dialogue)|Phaedrus]]''
* ''[[Symposium (Plato dialogue)|Symposium]]''
* ''[[Republic (Plato)|Republic]]''
* ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]''
* ''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]''
==== Late dialogues ====
The ''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]'' presents a series of criticisms of the theory of Forms which are widely taken to indicate Plato's abandonment of the doctrine. Some recent publications (e.g., Meinwald (1991)) have challenged this characterisation. In most of the remaining dialogues the theory is either absent or at least appears under a different guise in discussions about kinds or classes of things (the ''[[Timaeus]]'' may be an important, and hence controversially placed, exception). Socrates is either absent or a minor figure in the discussion. An apparently new method for doing dialectic known as "collection and division" is also featured, most notably in the ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]'' and ''[[Statesman]]'', explicitly for the first time in the ''[[Phaedrus (dialogue)|Phaedrus]]'', and possibly in the ''[[Philebus]]''. A basic description of collection and division would go as follows: interlocutors attempt to discern the similarities and differences among things in order to get clear idea about what they in fact are. One understanding, suggested in some passages of the ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]'', is that this is what philosophy is always in the business of doing, and is doing even in the early dialogues.
The late dialogues are also an important place to look for Plato's mature thought on most of the issues dealt with in the earlier dialogues. There is much work still to be done by scholars on the working out of what these views are. The later works are agreed to be difficult and challenging pieces of philosophy. On the whole they are more sober and logical than earlier works, but may hold out the promise of steps towards a solution to problems which were systematically laid out in prior works.
* ''[[Sophist (dialogue)|Sophist]]''
* ''[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]''
* ''[[Philebus]]''
* ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]''
* ''[[Critias (dialogue)|Critias]]''
* ''[[Laws (dialogue)|Laws]]''
=== Loeb Classical Library ===
[[James Loeb]] provided a very popular edition of Plato's works, still in print in the [[21st century]]: see [[Loeb Classical Library#Plato]] for how Plato's works were named in Loeb's publications.
{{academia
| teachers=[[Socrates]]
| students=[[Aristotle]]</br>[[Theophrastus]]
}}
== See also ==
* [[List of publications in philosophy#Western philosophy|Important publications in Western philosophy]]
* [[Mitchell Miller]]
* [[Eric A. Havelock]]
* [[Alexander Nehamas]]
* [[Platonic love]]
* [[The Seventh Letter of Plato]]
* [[Simulated reality]]
== Footnotes ==
<references/>
== References ==
*Bakalis, Nikolaos (2005). ''Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments'', Trafford Publishing ISBN 1-4120-4843-5
* {{cite book | author=Cooper, John M. & Hutchinson, D. S. (Eds.) | title=Plato: Complete Works | publisher=Hackett Publishing Co., Inc | year=1997 | id=ISBN 0-87220-349-2}}
* {{cite book | author=Durant, Will | title=The Story of Philosophy | publisher=Simon & Schuster | year=1926 | id=ISBN 0-671-69500-2}}
* [[Jacques Derrida|Derrida, Jacques]] (1972). ''La dissémination'', Paris: Seuil. (esp. cap.: ''La Pharmacie de Platon'', 69-199) ISBN 2-02-001958-2
* Fine, Gail (2000). ''Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology'' Oxford University Press, USA, ISBN 0-19-875206-7
* [[W. K. C. Guthrie|Guthrie, W. K. C.]] (1986). ''A History of Greek Philosophy (Plato - The Man & His Dialogues - Earlier Period)'', Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-31101-2
* [[W. K. C. Guthrie|Guthrie, W. K. C.]] (1986). ''A History of Greek Philosophy (Later Plato & the Academy)'' Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-31102-0
*Havelock, Eric (2005). ''Preface to Plato (History of the Greek Mind)'', Belknap Press, ISBN 0-674-69906-8
* {{cite book | author=Hamilton, Edith & Cairns, Huntington (Eds.) | title=The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Including the Letters | publisher=Princeton Univ. Press | year=1961 | id=ISBN 0-691-09718-6}}
*Irwin, Terence (1995). ''Plato's Ethics'', Oxford University Press, USA, ISBN 0-19-508645-7
* {{ cite book | author=Lundberg, Phillip |title=Tallyho - The Hunt for Virtue: Beauty, Truth and Goodness - Nine Dialogues by Plato |publisher=AuthorHouse | year=2005 | id=ISBN 1-4184-4976-8 |}}
* {{cite book | author=Jackson, Roy | title=Plato: A Beginner's Guide | ___location=London | publisher=Hoder & Stroughton | year=2001 | id=ISBN 0-340-80385-1}}
* {{cite book | author=Kraut, Richard (Ed.) | title=The Cambridge Companion to Plato | publisher=Cambridge University Press | year=1993 | id=ISBN 0-521-43610-9}}
* {{cite book | author=Livergood, Norman | title=Portals to Higher Consciousness | publisher=Dandelion Books | year=2006 | id=ISBN 1-893302-92-X }}
* {{cite book | author=Melchert, Norman | title=The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy | publisher=McGraw Hill | year=2002 | id=ISBN 0-19-517510-7}}
* {{cite book | author=Meinwald, Constance Chu | title=Plato's Parmenides | publisher=Oxford University Press | year=1991 | id=ISBN 0-19-506445-3 }}
* {{cite book | author=[[John Sallis|Sallis, John]] | title=Being and Logos: Reading the Platonic Dialogues | publisher=Indiana University Press | year=1996 | id=ISBN 0-253-21071-2 }}
* {{cite book | author=[[John Sallis|Sallis, John]] | title=Chorology: On Beginning in Plato's "Timaeus" | publisher=Indiana University Press | year=1999 | id=ISBN 0-253-21308-8 }}
* Taylor, A. E. (2001). ''Plato: The Man and His Work'', Dover Publications, ISBN 0-486-41605-4
* [[Gregory Vlastos|Vlastos, Gregory]] (1981). ''Platonic Studies'', Princeton University Press, ISBN 0-691-10021-7
* [[Oxford University Press]] publishes scholarly editions of Plato's Greek texts in the ''[[Oxford Classical Texts]]'' series, and some translations in the ''Clarendon Plato Series''.
* [[Harvard University Press]] publishes the hardbound series ''[[Loeb Classical Library#Plato|Loeb Classical Library]]'', containing Plato's works in [[Greek language|Greek]], with English translations on facing pages.
* {{cite book | author=Smith, William. | title=Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology | publisher=University of Michigan/Online version | year=1867 — original }}
*''Aspects of antiquity: Discoveries and Controversies'' by M.I. Finley, issued 1969 by The Viking Press, Inc.
*''Interpreting Plato: The Dialogues as Drama'' by James A. Arieti, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc. ISBN 0-8476-7662-5
== External links ==
{{wikisource|el:Πλάτων|Πλάτων}}
{{wikiquote}}
{{Commonscat|Plato}}
*Works available on-line
** {{gutenberg author | id=Plato | name=Plato}}
*** [http://www.gutenberg.org/catalog/world/authrec?fk_authors=688 Spurious and doubtful works] at [[Project Gutenberg]]
** [http://www.ellopos.net/elpenor/greek-texts/ancient-greece/plato/default.asp Plato complete works, annotated and searchable, at ELPENOR]
**[http://www.davemckay.co.uk/philosophy/plato/ Complete Dialogues, Letters and Epigrams of Plato Online, with multiple English translations]
** {{PerseusAuthor|Plato}}
** [http://librivox.org/euthyphro-by-plato/ A free audiobook of Plato's ''Euthyphro'']
* Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato/ Plato]
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-ethics/ Plato's Ethics]
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-friendship/ Friendship and Eros]
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-metaphysics/ Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology]
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-utopia/ Plato on Utopia]
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-rhetoric/ Rhetoric and Poetry]
* Other Articles:
** [http://www.ellopos.net/elpenor/greek-texts/ancient-greece/guthrie-plato.asp Excerpt from W.K.C. Guthrie, ''A History of Greek Philosophy, vol. IV, Plato: the man and his dialogues, earlier period'', Cambridge University Press, 1989, pp. 8-38]
** [http://plato-dialogues.org/plato.htm Website on Plato and his works: Plato and his dialogues by Bernard Suzanne]
** [http://journal.ilovephilosophy.com/Article/Are-there-really-Platonic-forms-/53 Are there really Platonic forms?]
** [http://www.worldfuturefund.org/wffmaster/Reading/Quotes/plato.htm "Plato and Totalitarianism: A Documentary Study"]
** [http://www.hermes-press.com/Perennial_Tradition/academy_index.htm The New Academy]
{{Persondata
|NAME=Plato
|ALTERNATIVE NAMES=Aristocles, Plátōn, Πλάτων (Greek)
|SHORT DESCRIPTION=[[Greeks|Greek]] [[philosopher]], a student of [[Socrates]], writer of philosophical dialogues, and founder of the [[Academy]]
|DATE OF BIRTH=c. [[427 BC]]
|PLACE OF BIRTH=[[Athens]]
|DATE OF DEATH=c. [[347 BC]]
|PLACE OF DEATH=
}}
[[Category:Platonism|*]]
[[Category:Ancient Greek philosophers]]
[[Category:Philosophers of language|Plato]]
[[Category:Philosophers of law|Plato]]
[[Category:Political philosophers]]
[[Category:Ancient Greek physicists]]
[[Category:Ancient Athenians]]
[[Category:Ancient Greek vegetarians|Plato]]
[[Category:427 BC births]]
[[Category:347 BC deaths]]
{{Link FA|fi}}
[[cdo:Báik-lăk-dù]]
[[af:Plato]]
[[ar:أفلاطون]]
[[ast:Platón]]
[[az:Platon]]
[[bn:প্লেটো]]
[[ba:Платон]]
[[bs:Platon]]
[[bg:Платон]]
[[ca:Plató]]
[[cs:Platón]]
[[cy:Platon]]
[[da:Platon]]
[[de:Platon]]
[[et:Platon]]
[[el:Πλάτων]]
[[es:Platón]]
[[eo:Platono]]
[[eu:Platon]]
[[fa:افلاطون]]
[[fr:Platon]]
[[ga:Platón]]
[[gl:Platón]]
[[ko:플라톤]]
[[hr:Platon]]
[[io:Platon]]
[[ilo:Plato]]
[[id:Plato]]
[[is:Platon]]
[[it:Platone]]
[[he:אפלטון]]
[[jv:Plato]]
[[ka:პლატონი]]
[[la:Plato]]
[[lv:Platons]]
[[lt:Platonas]]
[[hu:Platón]]
[[mk:Платон]]
[[ms:Plato]]
[[nl:Plato (filosoof)]]
[[ja:プラトン]]
[[no:Platon]]
[[nn:Platon]]
[[ps:افلاطون]]
[[nds:Platon]]
[[pl:Platon]]
[[pt:Platão]]
[[ro:Platon]]
[[ru:Платон]]
[[sq:Platoni]]
[[scn:Platuni]]
[[simple:Plato]]
[[sk:Platón]]
[[sl:Platon]]
[[sr:Платон]]
[[sh:Platon]]
[[fi:Platon]]
[[sv:Platon]]
[[ta:பிளேட்டோ]]
[[th:เพลโต]]
[[vi:Platon]]
[[tg:Афлотун]]
[[tpi:Platon]]
[[tr:Eflatun]]
[[uk:Платон]]
[[ur:افلاطون]]
[[wa:Platon]]
[[zh:柏拉图]]
|