Uninterpreted function: Difference between revisions

Content deleted Content added
Discussion: tweak to same ref
m WP:ADOPTYPO boolean -> Boolean
 
(24 intermediate revisions by 15 users not shown)
Line 1:
{{Short description|Type of function in mathematical logic}}
{{Context|date=October 2009}}
 
In [[mathematical logic]], an '''uninterpreted function'''<ref>Bryant,{{Cite Lahiri,book Seshia| (2002)chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/3-540-45657-0_7.pdf |doi = 10.1007/3-540-45657-0_7|chapter = "Modeling and verifyingVerifying systemsSystems usingUsing a logicLogic of counterCounter arithmeticArithmetic with lambdaLambda expressionsExpressions and uninterpretedUninterpreted functions".Functions|title = ''Computer Aided Verification''|volume = '''2404/|pages = 78–92|series = Lecture Notes in Computer Science|year = 2002''',|last1 106&ndash;122= Bryant|first1 = Randal E.|last2 = Lahiri|first2 = Shuvendu K.|last3 = Seshia|first3 = Sanjit A.|isbn = 978-3-540-43997-4| s2cid=9471360 }}</ref> or '''function symbol'''<ref>{{cite book |last1=Baader |first1=Franz |authorlink1=Franz Baader |last2=Nipkow |first2=Tobias |authorlink2=Tobias Nipkow |year=1999 |title=Term Rewriting and All That |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-77920-3 |page=34}}</ref> is one that has no other property than its name and ''[[Arity|n-ary]]'' form. Function symbols are used, together with constants and variables, to form [[term (logic)|terms]].
 
The '''theory of uninterpreted functions''' is also sometimes called the '''free theory''', because it is freely generated, and thus a [[free object]], or the '''empty theory''', being the [[theory (mathematical logic)|theory]] having an empty set of [[sentence (mathematical logic)|sentences]] (in analogy to an [[initial algebra]]). Theories with a non-empty set of equations are known as [[equational theory|equational theories]]. The [[satisfiability]] problem for free theories is solved by [[syntactic unification]]; algorithms for the latter are used by interpreters for various computer languages, such as [[Prolog]]. Syntactic unification is also used in algorithms for the satisfiability problem for certain other equational theories, see [[E-Unification]] and [[Narrowing (computer science)|Narrowing]].
 
==Example==
As an example of uninterpreted functions for [[SMT-LIB]], if this input is given to an [[Satisfiability modulo theories|SMT solver]]:
An [[array data structure|array]] can be specified by the following equational [[axiom]]:<ref group=note>Here, ''select''(''a'',''i'') informally designates the value of the ''i''th element of ''a'', written e.g. in [[C (programming language)|C]] as <code lang="C">a[i]</code>, while ''store''(''a'',''i'',''v'') informally designates the array resulting from writing the value ''v'' to the ''i''th element of ''a'', written in C as <code lang="C">a[i]=v</code>.
<syntaxhighlight lang="text" line="1">
The axiom then informally means that the value obtained by the statements <code lang="C">a[i]=v;return a[j];</code> equals <code lang="C">v</code> if <code lang="C">i</code>=<code lang="C">j</code>, and <code lang="C">a[j]</code>, else.</ref>
(declare-fun f (Int) Int)
 
(assert (= (f 10) 1))
: ''select''(''store''(''a'',''i'',''v''),''j'') = (if ''i'' = ''j'' then ''v'' else ''select''(''a'',''j''))
</syntaxhighlight>
 
the SMT solver would return "This input is satisfiable". That happens because <code>f</code> is an uninterpreted function (i.e., all that is known about <code>f</code> is its [[Signature (logic)|signature]]), so it is possible that <code>f(10) = 1</code>. But by applying the input below:
This axiom can be used to deduce<ref group=note>This deduction corresponds to the computation of the value obtained by <code lang="C">a[1]=-1;a[2]=-2;return a[1];</code></ref>
<syntaxhighlight lang="text" line="1">
 
(declare-fun f (Int) Int)
: ''select''(''store''(''store''(''a'',1,−1),2,−2),1)
(assert (= (f 10) 1))
:: = ''select''(''store''(''a'',1,−1),1)
(assert (= (f 10) 42))
:: = −1
</syntaxhighlight>
 
the SMT solver would return "This input is unsatisfiable". That happens because <code>f</code>, being a function, can never return different values for the same input.
Note that this reasoning did ''not'' use any 'definition' or [[interpretation (logic)|interpretation]] for the functions ''select'' and ''store''. All that is known is the axiom.
 
==Discussion==
The [[decision problem]] for free theories is particularly important, asbecause many theories can be reduced toby it;.<ref>{{cite thebook above|last1=de exampleMoura is|first1=Leonardo the|last2=Bjørner prototypical|first2=Nikolaj example|title=Formal ofmethods the: theoryfoundations ofand [[arrayapplications data: structure|arrays]],12th whereBrazilian 'select'Symposium andon 'store'Formal areMethods, theSBMF canonical2009, arrayGramado, accessBrazil, functions.<ref>{{citeAugust proceedings19-21, |last=McCarthy2009 |first=John: revised selected papers |yeardate=19622009 |titlepublisher=IFIP CongressSpringer |chapter___location=Towards a Mathematical Science of ComputationBerlin |publisherisbn=North978-Holland3-642-10452-7 |chapter-url=httphttps://citeseerxleodemoura.istgithub.psu.eduio/viewdocfiles/summary?doi=10sbmf09.1.1.79.8613 |pages=21–28pdf}}</ref>{{citation needed|reason=The given reference neither mentions 'array', nor 'store', nor 'select'. Apparently it doesn't handle the example.|date=May 2014}}
 
Free theories can be solved by searching for [[common subexpression]]s to form the [[congruence closure]].{{clarify|reason=Indicate about solving which problem in free theories the sentence is supposed to speak. E.g. to solve the satisfiability problem of conjunctions of equations, the Martelli-Montanari syntactic unification algorithm suffices, neither common subexpressions nor congruence closures are needed. Maybe, satisfiability of arbitrary booleanBoolean combinations of equations is meant?|date=May 2014}} Solvers include [[satisfiability modulo theories]] solvers.
 
== See also ==
Line 28:
* [[Initial algebra]]
* [[Term algebra]]
* [[Theory of pure equality]]
 
==Notes==
Line 33 ⟶ 34:
 
==References==
{{Reflist}}
 
{{reflist}}
[[Category:Specification languages]]
 
{{Mathematical logic}}
{{Formalmethods-stub}}
 
[[Category:Specification languages]]
{{Formalmethods-stub}}