Content deleted Content added
Joel Brennan (talk | contribs) |
m →Related definitions: semicolon is traditional symbol for composition of relations |
||
(19 intermediate revisions by 10 users not shown) | |||
Line 1:
{{Short description|none}}
This article examines the implementation of mathematical concepts in [[set theory]]. The implementation of a number of basic mathematical concepts is carried out in parallel in [[ZFC]] (the dominant set theory) and in [[New Foundations|NFU]], the version of Quine's [[New Foundations]] shown to be consistent by [[R. B. Jensen]] in 1969 (here understood to include at least axioms of [[Axiom of infinity|Infinity]] and [[Axiom of choice|Choice]]).
Line 43 ⟶ 44:
== Relations ==
[[Relation (mathematics)|Relations]] are sets whose members are all [[ordered pair]]s. Where possible, a relation <math>R</math> (understood as a [[binary predicate]]) is implemented as <math>\{(x,y) \mid x R y\}</math> (which may be written as <math>\{z \mid \pi_1(z) R \pi_2(z)\}</math>).
In
to be sets (but may be harmlessly reified as [[proper class]]es). In
need to have the same type (because they appear as projections of the same pair), but also
successive types (because <math>x</math> is considered as an element of <math>y</math>).
Line 57 ⟶ 58:
The '''___domain''' of <math>R</math> is the set <math>\left\{x : \exists y \left(xRy\right)\right\}</math>.
The '''range''' of <math>R</math> is the ___domain of the converse of <math>R</math>. That is, the set <math>\left\{y : \exists x \left(xRy\right)\right\}</math>.
The '''field''' of <math>R</math> is the [[union (set theory)|union]] of the ___domain and range of <math>R</math>.
Line 65 ⟶ 66:
The '''downward closure''' of a member <math>x</math> of the field of <math>R</math> is the smallest set <math>D</math> containing <math>x</math>, and containing each <math>zRy</math> for each <math>y \in D</math> (i.e., including the preimage of each of its elements with respect to <math>R</math> as a subset.)
The '''[[relation composition|relative product]]''' <math>R
Notice that with our formal definition of a binary relation, the range and codomain of a relation are not distinguished
In
▲Notice that the range and codomain of a relation are not distinguished: this could be done by representing a relation <math>R</math> with codomain <math>B</math> as <math>\left(R, B\right)</math>, but our development will not require this.
▲In [[ZFC]], any relation whose ___domain is a subset of a set <math>A</math> and whose range is a subset of a set <math>B</math> will be a set, since the [[cartesian product]] <math>A \times B = \left\{\left(a, b\right) : a \in A \wedge b \in B\right\}</math> is a set (being a subclass of <math>\mathcal{P}\!\left(A \cup B\right)</math>), and ''Separation'' provides for the existence of <math>\left\{\left(x, y\right) \in A \times B : xRy\right\}</math>. In [[New Foundations|NFU]], some relations with global scope (such as equality and subset) can be implemented as sets. In NFU, bear in mind that <math>x</math> and <math>y</math> are three types lower than <math>R</math> in <math>xRy</math> (one type lower if a type-level ordered pair is used).
=== Properties and kinds of relations ===
*'''[[Reflexive relation|Reflexive]]''' if <math>xRx</math> for every <math>x</math> in the field of <math>R</math>.
* '''[[Symmetric relation|Symmetric]]''' if <math>\forall x, y \,(xRy \to yRx)</math>.
Line 82 ⟶ 81:
* '''Extensional''' if for every <math>x, y</math> in the field of <math>R</math>, <math>x = y</math> if and only if <math>x</math> and <math>y</math> have the same preimage under <math>R</math>.
Relations having certain combinations of the above properties have standard names. A binary relation <math>R</math> is:
* An '''[[equivalence relation]]''' if <math>R</math> is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive.
Line 91 ⟶ 90:
== Functions ==
A
Indeed, no matter which set we consider to be the codomain of a function, the function does not change as a set since by definition it is just a set of ordered pairs. That is, a function does not determine its codomain by our definition. If one finds this unappealing then one can instead define a function as the ordered pair <math>(f, B)</math>, where <math>f</math> is a functional relation and <math>B</math> is its codomain, but we do not take this approach in this article (more elegantly, if one first defines ordered triples - for example as <math>(x, y, z) = (x, (y, z))</math>- then one could define a function as the ordered triple <math>(f, A, B)</math> so as to also include the ___domain). Note that the same issue exists for relations: outside of formal set theory we usually say "Let <math>R \subseteq A \times B</math> be a binary relation", but formally <math>R</math> is a set of ordered pairs such that <math>\text{dom}\,R \subseteq A</math> and <math>\text{ran}\,R \subseteq B</math>.
The function <math>I\!\left(x\right) = x</math> is not a set in [[ZFC]] because it is 'too large.' <math>I\!\left(x\right)</math> is, however, a set in NFU. The function (predicate) <math>S\!\left(x\right) = \left\{x\right\}</math> is neither a function nor a set in either theory; in ZFC, this is true because such a set would be too large, and, in NFU, this is true because its definition would not be [[Stratified formula#In set theory|stratified]]. Moreover, <math>S\!\left(x\right)</math> can be proved not to exist in NFU (see the resolution of Cantor's paradox in [[New Foundations]].)▼
In NFU, <math>x</math> has the same type as <math>F\!\left(x\right)</math>, and <math>F</math> is three types higher than <math>F\!\left(x\right)</math> (one type higher, if a type-level ordered pair is used). To solve this problem, one could define <math>F\left[A\right]</math> as <math>\left\{y : \exists x\,\left(x \in A \wedge y = F\!\left(x\right)\right)\right\}</math> for any set <math>A</math>, but this is more conveniently written as <math>\left\{F\!\left(x\right) : x \in A\right\}</math>. Then, if <math>A</math> is a set and <math>F</math> is any functional relation, the [[Axiom of replacement|Axiom of Replacement]] assures that <math>F\left[A\right]</math> is a set in [[ZFC]]. In NFU, <math>F\left[A\right]</math> and <math>A</math> now have the same type, and <math>F</math> is two types higher than <math>F\left[A\right]</math> (the same type, if a type-level ordered pair is used).
▲The function <math>I</math> such that <math>I\!\left(x\right) = x</math> is not a set in
=== Operations on functions ===
Let <math>f</math> and <math>g</math> be arbitrary functions. The '''[[function composition|composition]]''' of <math>f</math> and <math>g</math>, <math>g \circ f</math>, is defined as the relative product <math>f
=== Special kinds of function ===
▲If <math>f</math> is a function from <math>A</math> to <math>B</math>, <math>f</math> is a:
* '''[[Injective function|Injection]]''' from <math>A</math> to <math>B</math> if the [[image (mathematics)|image]]s under <math>f</math> of distinct members of <math>A</math> are distinct members of <math>B</math>.
* '''[[Surjection]]''' from <math>A</math> to <math>B</math> if the range of <math>f</math> is <math>B</math>.
* '''[[Bijection]]''' from <math>A</math> to <math>B</math> if <math>f</math> is both an injection and a surjection.
Defining functions as ordered pairs <math>(f, B)</math> or ordered triples <math>(f, A, B)</math> has the advantages that we do not have to introduce the terminology of being a function "from <math>A</math> to <math>B</math>", and that we can speak of "being surjective" outright as opposed to only being able to speak of "being surjective onto <math>B</math>".
== Size of sets ==
In both [[ZFC]] and [[New Foundations|NFU]], two sets ''A'' and ''B'' are the same size (or are '''[[equinumerous]]''') if and only if there is a [[
Similarly, define <math>|A| \leq |B|</math> as holding if and only if there is an [[Injective function|injection]] from ''A'' to ''B''.
It is straightforward to show that the relation of equinumerousness is an [[equivalence relation]]: equinumerousness of ''A'' with ''A'' is witnessed by <math>i_A</math>; if ''f'' witnesses <math>|A|=|B|</math>, then <math>f^{-1}</math> witnesses <math>|B|=|A|</math>; and if ''f'' witnesses <math>|A|=|B|</math> and ''g'' witnesses <math>|B|=|C|</math>, then <math>g\circ f</math> witnesses <math>|A|=|C|</math>.
It can be shown that <math>|A| \leq |B|</math> is a [[linear order]] on abstract cardinals, but not on sets. Reflexivity is obvious and transitivity is proven just as for equinumerousness. The [[Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem|Schröder–Bernstein theorem]], provable in [[ZFC]] and [[New Foundations|NFU]] in an entirely standard way, establishes that
*<math>|A| \leq |B| \wedge |B| \leq |A| \rightarrow |A| = |B|</math>
(this establishes antisymmetry on cardinals), and
Line 150 ⟶ 149:
(But note that this style of definition is feasible for the ZFC numerals as well, but more circuitous: the form of the [[New Foundations|NFU]] definition facilitates set manipulations while the form of the ZFC definition facilitates recursive definitions, but either theory supports either style of definition).
The two implementations are quite different. In ZFC, choose a [[representative (mathematics)|representative]] of each finite cardinality (the equivalence classes themselves are too large to be sets); in NFU the equivalence classes themselves are sets, and are thus an obvious choice for objects to stand in for the cardinalities. However, the arithmetic of the two theories is identical: the same abstraction is implemented by these two superficially different approaches.
== Equivalence relations and partitions ==
Line 199 ⟶ 198:
Cardinal numbers are defined in [[New Foundations|NFU]] in a way which generalizes the definition of natural
number: for any set ''A'', <math>|A|
In [[ZFC]], these equivalence classes are too large as usual. Scott's trick could be used (and indeed is used in [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory|ZF]]), <math>|A|</math> is usually defined as the smallest order type (here a von Neumann ordinal) of a well-ordering of ''A'' (that every set can be well-ordered follows from
Line 314 ⟶ 313:
==References==
*[[Keith Devlin]], 1994. ''The Joy of Sets'', 2nd ed. Springer-Verlag.
*Holmes, Randall, 1998. ''[
*Potter, Michael, 2004. ''Set Theory and its Philosophy'', 2nd ed. Oxford Univ. Press.
*Suppes, Patrick, 1972. ''Axiomatic Set Theory''. Dover.
*Tourlakis, George, 2003. ''Lectures in Logic and Set Theory, Vol. 2''. Cambridge Univ. Press.
==
* [http://us.metamath.org/ Metamath:] A web site devoted to an ongoing derivation of mathematics from the axioms of ZFC and [[first-order logic]].
* [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]:
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/quine-nf Quine's New Foundations]—by Thomas Forster.
** [http://setis.library.usyd.edu.au/stanford/entries/settheory-alternative/ Alternative axiomatic set theories]—by Randall Holmes.
* Randall Holmes: [
{{Mathematical logic}}
[[Category:Large-scale mathematical formalization projects]]▼
[[Category:Formalism (deductive)]]▼
[[Category:Mathematical logic]]
[[Category:Set theory]]
▲[[Category:Formalism (deductive)]]
▲[[Category:Large-scale mathematical formalization projects]]
|