Content deleted Content added
m Bot: link syntax |
Citation bot (talk | contribs) Altered volume. Add: doi, issue, authors 1-1. Removed parameters. Some additions/deletions were parameter name changes. | Use this bot. Report bugs. | Suggested by Abductive | Category:Order theory | #UCB_Category 105/179 |
||
(25 intermediate revisions by 22 users not shown) | |||
Line 1:
{{Short description|Theorem in order theory and lattice theory}}
{{otheruses4|Kleene's fixed-point theorem in lattice theory|the fixed-point theorem in computability theory|Kleene's recursion theorem}}
[[File:Kleene fixpoint svg.svg|thumb|Computation of the least fixpoint of ''f''(''x'') = {{sfrac|1|10}}''x''<sup>2</sup>+[[arctangent|atan]](''x'')+1 using Kleene's theorem in the real [[interval (mathematics)|interval]] [0,7] with the usual order]]
In the [[mathematics|mathematical]] areas of [[order theory|order]] and [[lattice theory]], the '''Kleene fixed-point theorem''', named after American mathematician [[Stephen Cole Kleene]], states the following:
:''
The '''ascending Kleene chain''' of ''f'' is the [[chain (order theory)|chain]]
:<math>\bot
obtained by [[iterated function|iterating]] ''f'' on the [[least element]] ⊥ of ''L''. Expressed in a formula, the theorem states that
Line 14 ⟶ 16:
where <math>\textrm{lfp}</math> denotes the least fixed point.
does not consider how fixed points can be computed by iterating ''f'' from some seed (also, it pertains to [[monotone function]]s on [[complete lattices]]), this result is often attributed to [[Alfred Tarski]] who proves it for additive functions.<ref>{{cite journal | author=Alfred Tarski | url=http://projecteuclid.org/Dienst/UI/1.0/Summarize/euclid.pjm/1103044538 | title=A lattice-theoretical fixpoint theorem and its applications | journal = [[Pacific Journal of Mathematics]] | volume=5 | year=1955 | issue=2 | pages=285–309| doi=10.2140/pjm.1955.5.285 }}, page 305.</ref> Moreover, the Kleene fixed-point theorem can be extended to [[monotone function]]s using transfinite iterations.<ref>{{cite journal | author=Patrick Cousot and Radhia Cousot | url=https://projecteuclid.org/euclid.pjm/1102785059 | title=Constructive versions of Tarski's fixed point theorems | journal = Pacific Journal of Mathematics | volume=82 | year=1979 | issue=1 | pages=43–57| doi=10.2140/pjm.1979.82.43 }}</ref>
== Proof ==
Source:<ref>{{Cite book|title=Mathematical Theory of Domains by V. Stoltenberg-Hansen|last1=Stoltenberg-Hansen|first1=V.|last2=Lindstrom|first2=I.|last3=Griffor|first3=E. R.|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=1994|isbn=0521383447|pages=[https://archive.org/details/mathematicaltheo0000stol/page/24 24]|language=en|doi=10.1017/cbo9781139166386|url=https://archive.org/details/mathematicaltheo0000stol/page/24}}</ref>
We first have to show that the ascending Kleene chain of
:'''Lemma
▲We first have to show that the ascending Kleene chain of ''f'' exists in L. To show that, we prove the following lemma:
▲:Lemma 1:''If L is CPO, and f : L → L is a Scott-continuous, then <math>f^n(\bot) \sqsubseteq f^{n+1}(\bot), n \in \mathbb{N}_0</math>
:* Assume n = 0. Then <math>f^0(\bot) = \bot \sqsubseteq f^1(\bot),</math>
:* Assume n > 0. Then we have to show that <math>f^n(\bot) \sqsubseteq f^{n+1}(\bot)</math>. By rearranging we get <math>f(f^{n-1}(\bot)) \sqsubseteq f(f^n(\bot))</math>. By inductive assumption, we know that <math>f^{n-1}(\bot) \sqsubseteq f^n(\bot)</math> holds, and because f is monotone (property of Scott-continuous functions), the result holds as well.▼
▲Proof by induction:
▲* Assume n = 0. Then <math>f^0(\bot) = \bot \sqsubseteq f^1(\bot)</math>, since ⊥ is the least element.
▲* Assume n > 0. Then we have to show that <math>f^n(\bot) \sqsubseteq f^{n+1}(\bot)</math>. By rearranging we get <math>f(f^{n-1}(\bot)) \sqsubseteq f(f^n(\bot))</math>. By inductive assumption, we know that <math>f^{n-1}(\bot) \sqsubseteq f^n(\bot)</math> holds, and because f is monotone (property of Scott-continuous functions), the result holds as well.
:<math>\mathbb{M} = \{ \bot, f(\bot), f(f(\bot)), \ldots\}.</math>
▲Immediate corollary of Lemma 1 is the existence of the chain.
First, we show that <math>m</math> is a fixed point, i.e. that <math>f(m) = m</math>. Because <math>f</math> is [[Scott continuity|Scott-continuous]], <math>f(\sup(\mathbb{M})) = \sup(f(\mathbb{M}))</math>, that is <math>f(m) = \sup(f(\mathbb{M}))</math>. Also, since <math>
The proof that <math>m</math> is in fact the ''least'' fixed point can be done by showing that any
== See also ==
* Other [[fixed-point theorem]]s
== References ==
{{Reflist}}
[[Category:Order theory]]
[[Category:Fixed-point theorems]]
|