Content deleted Content added
m →Physical approaches to collapse: hyphen |
→Mathematical description: Fixed typo: it's not a generic arrow (can be mixed up for a limit) but set elements being mapped by a transformation. Tags: Mobile edit Mobile app edit Android app edit App section source |
||
(40 intermediate revisions by 20 users not shown) | |||
Line 2:
{{for|the constraint-solving algorithm| Wave function collapse (algorithm)}}
{{Use American English|date=January 2019}}
[[File:Wave-particle duality.gif|thumb|Particle impacts during a [[double-slit experiment]]. The total [[interference pattern]] represents the original [[wave function]], while each particle impact represents an individual wave function collapse.]]
{{Quantum mechanics}}
In various [[Interpretations of quantum mechanics|interpretations]] of [[quantum mechanics]], '''wave function collapse''', also called '''reduction of the state vector
{{cite book
|author=J. von Neumann
Line 10 ⟶ 12:
|publisher=[[Springer (publisher)|Springer]]
|___location=Berlin
|language=de}}<br/>
:{{cite book
|author=J. von Neumann
Line 18 ⟶ 20:
|url-access=registration
|publisher=[[Princeton University Press]]
}}</ref>
In the [[Copenhagen interpretation]], wave function collapse connects quantum to classical models, with a special [[Copenhagen interpretation#Role of the observer|role for the observer]]. By contrast, [[Objective-collapse theory|objective-collapse]] proposes an origin in physical processes. In the [[many-worlds interpretation]], collapse does not exist; all wave function outcomes occur while [[quantum decoherence]] accounts for the appearance of collapse.
Calculations of [[quantum decoherence]] show that when a quantum system interacts with the environment, the superpositions ''apparently'' reduce to mixtures of classical alternatives. Significantly, the combined wave function of the system and environment continue to obey the Schrödinger equation throughout this ''apparent'' collapse.<ref name=Zurek>{{cite journal|last=Zurek|first=Wojciech Hubert|title=Quantum Darwinism|journal=Nature Physics|year=2009|volume=5|pages=181–188|doi=10.1038/nphys1202|arxiv = 0903.5082 |bibcode = 2009NatPh...5..181Z|issue=3|s2cid=119205282}}</ref> More importantly, this is not enough to explain ''actual'' wave function collapse, as decoherence does not reduce it to a single eigenstate.<ref name=Schlosshauer>{{cite journal|last=Schlosshauer|first=Maximilian|title=Decoherence, the measurement problem, and interpretations of quantum mechanics|journal=Rev. Mod. Phys.|year=2005|volume=76|issue=4|pages=1267–1305|doi=10.1103/RevModPhys.76.1267|arxiv = quant-ph/0312059 |bibcode = 2004RvMP...76.1267S |s2cid=7295619}}</ref><ref name="Stanford1">{{cite encyclopedia▼
| last = Fine▼
| first = Arthur▼
| title = The Role of Decoherence in Quantum Mechanics▼
| encyclopedia = Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy▼
| publisher = Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University website▼
| date = 2020▼
| url = https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-decoherence/▼
| format =▼
| doi =▼
| access-date = 11 April 2021}}</ref>▼
Historically, [[Werner Heisenberg]] was the first to use the idea of wave function reduction to explain quantum measurement.<ref>[[Werner Heisenberg|Heisenberg, W.]] (1927). Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik, ''Z. Phys.'' '''43''': 172–198. Translation as
==Mathematical description==
{{About||an explanation of the notation used|Bra–ket notation|details on this formalism|Quantum state}}
In quantum mechanics each measurable physical quantity of a quantum system is called an [[observable]] which, for example, could be the position <math>r</math> and the momentum <math>p</math> but also energy <math>E</math>, <math>z</math> components of spin (<math>s_{z}</math>), and so on. The observable acts as a [[linear mapping|linear function]] on the states of the system; its eigenvectors correspond to the quantum state (i.e. [[
<math display=block> | \psi \rangle = \sum_i c_i | \phi_i \rangle.</math>
The kets <math>\{| \phi_i \rangle\}</math> specify the different available quantum "alternatives", i.e., particular quantum states.
The [[wave function]] is a specific representation of a quantum state. Wave functions can therefore always be expressed as eigenstates of an observable though the converse is not necessarily true.
===Collapse===
To account for the experimental result that repeated measurements of a quantum system give the same results, the theory postulates a "collapse" or "reduction of the state vector" upon observation,<ref name=GriffithsSchroeter3rd>{{Cite book |
:<math> | \psi \rangle = \sum_i c_i | \phi_i \rangle \
|\psi'\rangle = |\phi_i\rangle.</math> where the arrow represents a measurement of the observable corresponding to the <math>\phi</math> basis.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Hall |first=Brian C. |title=Quantum theory for mathematicians |date=2013 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4614-7115-8 |series=Graduate texts in mathematics |___location=New York |page=68}}</ref>
For any single event, only one eigenvalue is measured, chosen randomly from among the possible values.
===Meaning of the expansion coefficients===
Line 52 ⟶ 46:
can be written as an (complex) overlap of the corresponding eigenstate and the quantum state:
<math display=block> c_i = \langle \phi_i | \psi \rangle .</math>
They are called the [[probability amplitude]]s. The [[
:<math>\langle \psi|\psi \rangle = \sum_i |c_i|^2 = 1.</math>
As examples, individual counts in a [[double slit experiment]] with electrons appear at random locations on the detector; after many counts are summed the distribution shows a wave interference pattern.<ref name="Bach Pope Liou Batelaan 2013 p=033018">{{cite journal | last1=Bach | first1=Roger | last2=Pope | first2=Damian | last3=Liou | first3=Sy-Hwang | last4=Batelaan | first4=Herman | title=Controlled double-slit electron diffraction | journal=New Journal of Physics | publisher=IOP Publishing | volume=15 | issue=3 | date=2013-03-13 | issn=1367-2630 | doi=10.1088/1367-2630/15/3/033018 | page=033018 | arxiv=1210.6243 | bibcode=2013NJPh...15c3018B | s2cid=832961 | url=https://iopscience.iop.org/article/10.1088/1367-2630/15/3/033018}}</ref> In a [[Stern-Gerlach experiment]]
This statistical aspect of quantum measurements differs fundamentally from [[classical mechanics]]. In quantum mechanics the only information we have about a system is its wave function and measurements of its wave function can only give statistical information.<ref name=GriffithsSchroeter3rd/>{{rp|17}}
==Terminology==
The two terms "reduction of the state vector" (or "state reduction" for short) and
The term "wave function" is typically used for a different mathematical representation of the quantum state, one that uses spatial coordinates also called the "position representation".<ref name=messiah/>{{rp|324}} When the wave function representation is used, the "reduction" is called "wave function collapse".
== The measurement problem ==
The
==Physical approaches to collapse==
Quantum theory offers no dynamical description of the "collapse" of the wave function. Viewed as a statistical theory, no description is expected. As Fuchs and Peres put it, "collapse is something that happens in our description of the system, not to the system itself".<ref name=FuchsPeresNo>{{Cite journal |
Various [[interpretations of quantum mechanics]] attempt to provide a physical model for collapse.<ref name=Stamatescu>{{Cite book |last=Stamatescu |first=Ion-Olimpiu |title=Compendium of Quantum Physics |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-3-540-70626-7_230 |
The significance ascribed to the wave function varies from interpretation to interpretation
===Quantum decoherence===
{{Main
Quantum decoherence explains why a system interacting with an environment transitions from being a [[Quantum state#Pure states as rays in a complex Hilbert space|pure state]], exhibiting superpositions, to a [[Quantum state#Mixed states|mixed state]], an incoherent combination of classical alternatives.<ref name="Stanford1" />
▲
▲ | last = Fine
▲ | first = Arthur
▲ | title = The Role of Decoherence in Quantum Mechanics
▲ | encyclopedia = Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
▲ | publisher = Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University website
▲ | date = 2020
▲ | url = https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-decoherence/
▲ | format =
▲ | doi =
▲ | access-date = 11 April 2021}}</ref>
==History==
The concept of wavefunction collapse was introduced by [[Werner Heisenberg]] in his 1927 paper on the [[uncertainty principle]], "Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik", and incorporated into the [[mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics]] by [[John von Neumann]], in his 1932 treatise ''Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik''.<ref name="C. Kiefer-2002">{{
|doi=10.3390/e19100513|bibcode=2017Entrp..19..513J |doi-access=free |hdl=2144/41814 |hdl-access=free }}</ref>
[[John von Neumann]]'s influential 1932 work ''[[Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics]]'' took a more formal approach, developing an "ideal" measurement scheme<ref name=HartleQMCosmology>Hartle, James B. [https://arxiv.org/pdf/1805.12246.pdf "The quantum mechanics of cosmology."] Notes from the lectures by the author at the 7th Jerusalem Winter School 1990 on Quantum Cosmology and Baby Universes. arXiv:1805.12246 (2018).</ref><ref name=SchlosshauerReview>{{Cite
▲von Neumann took a more formal approach, developing "ideal" measurement scheme<ref name=HartleQMCosmology>Hartle, James B. [https://arxiv.org/pdf/1805.12246.pdf "The quantum mechanics of cosmology."] Notes from the lectures by the author at the 7th Jerusalem Winter School 1990 on Quantum Cosmology and Baby Universes. arXiv:1805.12246 (2018).</ref><ref name=SchlosshauerReview>{{Cite book |last=Schlosshauer |first=Maximilian |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/RevModPhys.76.1267 |title=Decoherence, the measurement problem, and interpretations of quantum mechanics |date=2005-02-23 |volume=76 |pages=1267–1305 |language=en |doi=10.1103/RevModPhys.76.1267 |issn=0034-6861}}</ref>{{rp|1270|q=Note that von Neumann’s scheme is in sharp contrast to the Copenhagen interpretation, where measurement is not treated as a system-apparatus interaction described by the usual quantum-mechanical formalism, but instead as an independent component of the theory, to be represented entirely in fundamentally classical terms.}} that postulated that there were two processes of wave function change:
# The [[probability|probabilistic]], non-[[unitary transformation|unitary]], [[local realism|non-local]], discontinuous change brought about by observation and [[quantum measurement|measurement]] (state reduction or collapse).
# The [[deterministic]], unitary, continuous [[time evolution]] of an isolated system that obeys the [[Schrödinger equation]]
In 1957 [[Hugh Everett III]] proposed a model of quantum mechanics that dropped von Neumann's first postulate. Everett observed that the measurement apparatus was also a quantum system and its quantum interaction with the system under observation should determine the results. He proposed that the discontinuous change is instead a splitting of a wave function representing the universe.<ref name=SchlosshauerReview/>{{rp|1288}} While Everett's approach
Beginning in 1970 [[H. Dieter Zeh]] sought a detailed
By explicitly dealing with the interaction of object and measuring instrument, von Neumann<ref name="Grundlagen"/> described a quantum mechanical measurement scheme consistent with wave function collapse. However, he did not prove the ''necessity'' of such a collapse.
{{cite book
|author=W. Pauli
|