Wave function collapse: Difference between revisions

Content deleted Content added
Undid revision 1281944286 by Sydneyuk (talk) Sorry, the first word of the compound "quantum mechanics" should not be linked; the full combo was previously linked.
Mathematical description: Fixed typo: it's not a generic arrow (can be mixed up for a limit) but set elements being mapped by a transformation.
Tags: Mobile edit Mobile app edit Android app edit App section source
 
(6 intermediate revisions by 5 users not shown)
Line 2:
{{for|the constraint-solving algorithm| Wave function collapse (algorithm)}}
{{Use American English|date=January 2019}}
[[File:Wave-particle duality.gif|thumb|Particle impacts during a [[double-slit experiment]]. The total [[interference pattern]] represents the original [[wave function]], while each particle impact represents an individual wave function collapse.]]
{{Quantum mechanics}}
 
In various [[Interpretations of quantum mechanics|interpretations]] of [[quantum mechanics]], '''wave function collapse''', also called '''reduction of the state vector''',<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Penrose |first=Roger |date=May 1996 |title=On Gravity's role in Quantum State Reduction |url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/BF02105068 |journal=General Relativity and Gravitation |language=en |volume=28 |issue=5 |pages=581–600 |doi=10.1007/BF02105068 |bibcode=1996GReGr..28..581P |issn=0001-7701|url-access=subscription }}</ref> occurs when a [[wave function]]—initially in a [[quantum superposition|superposition]] of several [[eigenstates]]—reduces to a single eigenstate due to [[Fundamental interaction|interaction]] with the external world. This interaction is called an [[Observation (physics)|''observation'']] and is the essence of a [[measurement in quantum mechanics]], which connects the wave function with classical [[observable]]s such as [[position (vector)|position]] and [[momentum]]. Collapse is one of the two processes by which [[quantum system]]s evolve in time; the other is the continuous evolution governed by the [[Schrödinger equation]].<ref name="Grundlagen">
{{cite book
|author=J. von Neumann
Line 20 ⟶ 22:
}}</ref>
 
WhileIn standardthe quantum[[Copenhagen mechanics postulatesinterpretation]], wave function collapse to connectconnects quantum to classical models, somewith extensiona theoriesspecial propose[[Copenhagen physicalinterpretation#Role processesof thatthe causeobserver|role collapsefor the observer]]. TheBy contrast, [[Objective-collapse theory|objective-collapse]] proposes an origin in depthphysical studyprocesses. ofIn the [[quantummany-worlds decoherenceinterpretation]], hascollapse proposeddoes thatnot collapseexist; isall relatedwave tofunction theoutcomes interactionoccur of awhile [[quantum systemdecoherence]] withaccounts itsfor environmentthe appearance of collapse.
 
Historically, [[Werner Heisenberg]] was the first to use the idea of wave function reduction to explain quantum measurement.<ref>[[Werner Heisenberg|Heisenberg, W.]] (1927). Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik, ''Z. Phys.'' '''43''': 172–198. Translation as [https://ntrs.nasa.gov/archive/nasa/casi.ntrs.nasa.gov/19840008978.pdf "The actual content of quantum theoretical kinematics and mechanics"].</ref><ref name="C. Kiefer-2002" />
Line 33 ⟶ 35:
 
===Collapse===
To account for the experimental result that repeated measurements of a quantum system give the same results, the theory postulates a "collapse" or "reduction of the state vector" upon observation,<ref name=GriffithsSchroeter3rd>{{Cite book |lastlast1=Griffiths |firstfirst1=David J. |title=Introduction to quantum mechanics |last2=Schroeter |first2=Darrell F. |date=2018 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-1-107-18963-8 |edition=3 |___location=Cambridge; New York, NY}}</ref>{{rp|566|q=to account for the fact that an immediately repeated measurement yields the same result, we are forced to assume that the act of measurement collapses the wave function,}} abruptly converting an arbitrary state into a single component eigenstate of the observable:
:<math> | \psi \rangle = \sum_i c_i | \phi_i \rangle \rightarrowmapsto
|\psi'\rangle = |\phi_i\rangle.</math>
where the arrow represents a measurement of the observable corresponding to the <math>\phi</math> basis.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Hall |first=Brian C. |title=Quantum theory for mathematicians |date=2013 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4614-7115-8 |series=Graduate texts in mathematics |___location=New York |page=68}}</ref>
For any single event, only one eigenvalue is measured, chosen randomly from among the possible values.
Line 56 ⟶ 59:
 
== The measurement problem ==
The Schrödinger equation describes quantum systems but does not describe their measurement. Solution to the equations include all possible observable values for measurements, but measurements only result in one definite outcome. This difference is called the [[measurement problem]] of quantum mechanics. To predict measurement outcomes from quantum solutions, the orthodox interpretation of quantum theory postulates wave function collapse and uses the [[Born rule]] to compute the probable outcomes.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Zurek |first=Wojciech Hubert |date=2003-05-22 |title=Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/RevModPhys.75.715 |journal=Reviews of Modern Physics |language=en |volume=75 |issue=3 |pages=715–775 |doi=10.1103/RevModPhys.75.715 |issn=0034-6861|arxiv=quant-ph/0105127 |bibcode=2003RvMP...75..715Z }}</ref> Despite the widespread quantitative success of these postulates scientists remain dissatisfied and have sought more detailed physical models. Rather than suspending the Schrödinger equation during the process of measurement, the measurement apparatus should be included and governed by the laws of quantum mechanics.<ref>{{Cite book |lastlast1=Susskind |firstfirst1=Leonard |title=Quantum mechanics: the theoretical minimum; [what you need to know to start doing physics] |last2=Friedman |first2=Art |last3=Susskind |first3=Leonard |date=2014 |publisher=Basic Books |isbn=978-0-465-06290-4 |series=The theoretical minimum / Leonard Susskind and George Hrabovsky |___location=New York, NY}}</ref>{{rp|127}}
 
==Physical approaches to collapse==
Quantum theory offers no dynamical description of the "collapse" of the wave function. Viewed as a statistical theory, no description is expected. As Fuchs and Peres put it, "collapse is something that happens in our description of the system, not to the system itself".<ref name=FuchsPeresNo>{{Cite journal |lastlast1=Fuchs |firstfirst1=Christopher A. |last2=Peres |first2=Asher |date=2000-03-01 |title=Quantum Theory Needs No ‘Interpretation’'Interpretation' |url=https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/document?repid=rep1&type=pdf&doi=7596444653d614458ee7aea0422dabfc95ace3e6 |journal=Physics Today |language=en |volume=53 |issue=3 |pages=70–71 |doi=10.1063/1.883004 |bibcode=2000PhT....53c..70F |issn=0031-9228}}</ref>
 
Various [[interpretations of quantum mechanics]] attempt to provide a physical model for collapse.<ref name=Stamatescu>{{Cite book |last=Stamatescu |first=Ion-Olimpiu |title=Compendium of Quantum Physics |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-3-540-70626-7_230 |titlechapter=Wave Function Collapse |date=2009 |publisher=Springer Berlin Heidelberg |isbn=978-3-540-70622-9 |editor-last=Greenberger |editor-first=Daniel |___location=Berlin, Heidelberg |pages=813–822 |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-3-540-70626-7_230 |editor-last2=Hentschel |editor-first2=Klaus |editor-last3=Weinert |editor-first3=Friedel}}</ref>{{rp|816}} Three treatments of collapse can be found among the common interpretations. The first group includes hidden-variable theories like [[de Broglie–Bohm theory]]; here random outcomes only result from unknown values of hidden variables. Results from [[Bell test|tests]] of [[Bell's theorem]] shows that these variables would need to be non-local. The second group models measurement as quantum entanglement between the quantum state and the measurement apparatus. This results in a simulation of classical statistics called quantum decoherence. This group includes the [[many-worlds interpretation]] and [[consistent histories]] models. The third group postulates additional, but as yet undetected, physical basis for the randomness; this group includes for example the [[objective-collapse interpretation]]s. While models in all groups have contributed to better understanding of quantum theory, no alternative explanation for individual events has emerged as more useful than collapse followed by statistical prediction with the Born rule.<ref name=Stamatescu/>{{rp|819}}
 
The significance ascribed to the wave function varies from interpretation to interpretation and even within an interpretation (such as the [[Copenhagen interpretation]]). If the wave function merely encodes an observer's knowledge of the universe, then the wave function collapse corresponds to the receipt of new information. This is somewhat analogous to the situation in classical physics, except that the classical "wave function" does not necessarily obey a wave equation. If the wave function is physically real, in some sense and to some extent, then the collapse of the wave function is also seen as a real process, to the same extent.{{citation needed| reason=the ontological wave function literature should be represented, the paragraph based on Stamatescu is too compact now.|date=March 2024}}
Line 83 ⟶ 86:
 
==History==
The concept of wavefunction collapse was introduced by [[Werner Heisenberg]] in his 1927 paper on the [[uncertainty principle]], "Über den anschaulichen Inhalt der quantentheoretischen Kinematik und Mechanik", and incorporated into the [[mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics]] by [[John von Neumann]], in his 1932 treatise ''Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik''.<ref name="C. Kiefer-2002">{{Cite book |last=Kiefer |first=Claus |url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-3-662-10557-3_19 |title=Time, Quantum and Information. |date=2003 |publisher=Springer Berlin Heidelberg |isbn=978-3-642-07892-7 |editor-last=Castell |editor-first=Lutz |___location=Berlin, Heidelberg |pages=291–299 |language=en |chapter=On the Interpretation of Quantum Theory — from Copenhagen to the Present Day |doi=10.1007/978-3-662-10557-3_19 |arxiv=quant-ph/0210152 |editor-last2=Ischebeck |editor-first2=Otfried}}</ref> Heisenberg did not try to specify exactly what the collapse of the wavefunction meant. However, he emphasized that it should not be understood as a physical process.<ref>{{cite journal |author=G. Jaeger |year=2017 |title="Wave-Packet Reduction" and the Quantum Character of the Actualization of Potentia |journal=Entropy |volume=19 |issue=10 |pages=13
|doi=10.3390/e19100513|bibcode=2017Entrp..19..513J |doi-access=free |hdl=2144/41814 |hdl-access=free }}</ref> Niels Bohr never mentions wave function collapse in his published work, but he repeatedly cautioned that we must give up a "pictorial representation". Despite the differences between Bohr and Heisenberg, their views are often grouped together as the "Copenhagen interpretation", of which wave function collapse is regarded as a key feature.<ref>{{cite journal|title=Niels Bohr on the wave function and the classical/quantum divide |author=Henrik Zinkernagel |year=2016 |doi=10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.11.001 |journal=Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics |volume=53 |pages=9–19 |arxiv = 1603.00353|bibcode=2016SHPMP..53....9Z |s2cid=18890207 |quote=Among Bohr scholars it is common to assert that Bohr never mentions the wave function collapse (see e.g. Howard, 2004 and Faye, 2008). It is true that in Bohr’s published writings, he does not discuss the status or existence of this standard component in the popular image of the Copenhagen interpretation. }}</ref>
 
[[John von Neumann]]'s influential 1932 work ''[[Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics]]'' took a more formal approach, developing an "ideal" measurement scheme<ref name=HartleQMCosmology>Hartle, James B. [https://arxiv.org/pdf/1805.12246.pdf "The quantum mechanics of cosmology."] Notes from the lectures by the author at the 7th Jerusalem Winter School 1990 on Quantum Cosmology and Baby Universes. arXiv:1805.12246 (2018).</ref><ref name=SchlosshauerReview>{{Cite journal |last=Schlosshauer |first=Maximilian |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/RevModPhys.76.1267 |title=Decoherence, the measurement problem, and interpretations of quantum mechanics |journal=Reviews of Modern Physics |date=2005-02-23 |volume=76 |issue=4 |pages=1267–1305 |language=en |doi=10.1103/RevModPhys.76.1267 |issn=0034-6861|arxiv=quant-ph/0312059 |bibcode=2004RvMP...76.1267S }}</ref>{{rp|1270|q=Note that von Neumann’s scheme is in sharp contrast to the Copenhagen interpretation, where measurement is not treated as a system-apparatus interaction described by the usual quantum-mechanical formalism, but instead as an independent component of the theory, to be represented entirely in fundamentally classical terms.}} that postulated that there were two processes of wave function change:
 
# The [[probability|probabilistic]], non-[[unitary transformation|unitary]], [[local realism|non-local]], discontinuous change brought about by observation and [[quantum measurement|measurement]] (state reduction or collapse).
Line 93 ⟶ 96:
In 1957 [[Hugh Everett III]] proposed a model of quantum mechanics that dropped von Neumann's first postulate. Everett observed that the measurement apparatus was also a quantum system and its quantum interaction with the system under observation should determine the results. He proposed that the discontinuous change is instead a splitting of a wave function representing the universe.<ref name=SchlosshauerReview/>{{rp|1288}} While Everett's approach rekindled interest in foundational quantum mechanics, it left core issues unresolved. Two key issues relate to origin of the observed classical results: what causes quantum systems to appear classical and to resolve with the observed probabilities of the [[Born rule]].<ref name=SchlosshauerReview/>{{rp|1290}}<ref name=HartleQMCosmology/>{{rp|5}}
 
Beginning in 1970 [[H. Dieter Zeh]] sought a detailed quantum decoherence model for the discontinuous change without postulating collapse. Further work by [[Wojciech H. Zurek]] in 1980 lead eventually to a large number of papers on many aspects of the concept.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Camilleri |first=Kristian |date=2009-12-01 |title=A history of entanglement: Decoherence and the interpretation problem |url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S1355219809000562 |journal=Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics |series=On The History Of The Quantum |volume=40 |issue=4 |pages=290–302 |doi=10.1016/j.shpsb.2009.09.003 |bibcode=2009SHPMP..40..290C |issn=1355-2198|url-access=subscription }}</ref> Decoherence assumes that every quantum system interacts quantum mechanically with its environment and such interaction is not separable from the system, a concept called an "open system".<ref name=SchlosshauerReview/>{{rp|1273}} Decoherence has been shown to work very quickly and within a minimal environment, but as yet it has not succeeded in a providing a detailed model replacing the collapse postulate of orthodox quantum mechanics.<ref name=SchlosshauerReview/>{{rp|1302}}
 
By explicitly dealing with the interaction of object and measuring instrument, von Neumann<ref name="Grundlagen"/> described a quantum mechanical measurement scheme consistent with wave function collapse. However, he did not prove the ''necessity'' of such a collapse. Von Neumann's projection postulate was conceived based on experimental evidence available during the 1930s, in particular [[Compton scattering]]. Later work refined the notion of measurements into the more easily discussed ''first kind'', that will give the same value when immediately repeated, and the ''second kind'' that give different values when repeated.<ref>