Subobject classifier: Difference between revisions

Content deleted Content added
Dropped repeated adverb
Bender the Bot (talk | contribs)
m References: HTTP to HTTPS for Cornell University
 
(40 intermediate revisions by 20 users not shown)
Line 1:
In mathematics, especially in [[category theory]], a '''subobject classifier''' is a special object Ω of a category; such that, intuitively, the [[subobject]]s of anany object ''X'' in the category correspond to the morphisms from ''X'' to Ω. AsIn thetypical name suggestsexamples, whatthat amorphism subobjectassigns classifier does is"true" to identify/classifythe subobjectselements of athe givensubobject objectand according to which elements belong"false" to the subobjectother in question. Becauseelements of this''X.'' roleTherefore, thea subobject classifier is also referred toknown as thea "truth value object". In factand the wayconcept inis whichwidely theused subobjectin classifierthe classifiescategorical subobjectsdescription of alogic. givenNote object,however is by assigning the values true to elements belonging to thethat subobject inclassifiers question,are andoften falsemuch tomore elementscomplicated not belonging tothan the subobject.simple Thisbinary islogic whytruth thevalues subobject{true, classifier is widely used in the categorical description of logicfalse}.
 
== Introductory example ==
 
As an example, the set Ω = {0,1} is a subobject classifier in the [[category of sets]] and functions: to every subset ''A'' of ''S'' defined by the inclusion function&nbsp; '' j '' : '' U A'' → '' X S'' we can assign the function ''χ<sub>jA</sub>'' from '' X S'' to Ω that maps precisely the elements of ''UA'' to 1, and the elements outside ''A'' to 0 (seein other words, ''χ<sub>A</sub>'' is the [[indicator function|characteristic function]] of ''A''). EveryConversely, every function from ''XS'' to Ω arises in this fashion from precisely one subset ''UA''.
 
To be clearer, consider a [[subset]] ''A'' of ''S'' (''A'' ⊆ ''S''), where ''S'' is a set. The notion of being a subset can be expressed mathematically using the so-called characteristic function χ<sub>''A''</sub> : S → {0,1}, which is defined as follows:
Line 12:
\end{cases}</math>
 
(Here we interpret 1 as true and 0 as false.) The role of the characteristic function is to determine which elements belong or not to a certainthe subset ''A''. In fact, χ<sub>''A''</sub> is true precisely on the elements of ''A''.
 
In this way, the collection of all subsets of ''S'' and the collection of all maps from ''S'' to Ω = {0,1} are [[isomorphic]].
Recall that in category theory, a subobject is actually a pair consisting of an object and a [[monomorphism|monic arrows]] (interpreted as the inclusion into another object). Accordingly, true refers to the object 1 and the arrow: '''true''': {0} → {0, 1} which maps 0 to 1. The subset ''A'' can now be defined as the [[pullback (category theory)|pullback]] of '''true''' and the characteristic function χ<sub>''A''</sub>, also written ''A'' = χ<sub>''A''</sub><sup>−1</sup>(1)
[[Image:SubobjectClassifier-01.png|center]]
The category '''Set''' with its subobject classifier satisfy the following property:
:The collection of all subsets of S denoted by <math>\mathcal{P}(S)</math>, and the collection of all maps from S to the set {0, 1} = 2 denoted by 2<sup>''S''</sup> are [[isomorphic]] i.e. the function <math>y:\mathcal{P}(S)\rightarrow2^S</math>, which in terms of single elements of <math>\mathcal{P}(S)</math> is ''A'' → χ<sub>''A''</sub>, is a [[bijection]].
 
RecallTo categorize this notion, recall that, in category theory, a subobject is actually represented by a pair consisting of an object ''A'' and a [[monomorphism|monic arrowsarrow]] ''A → S'' (interpreted as the inclusion into another object ''S''). Accordingly, '''true''' refers to the objectelement 1, andwhich is selected by the arrow: '''true''': {0} → {0, 1} whichthat maps 0 to 1. The subset ''A'' of ''S'' can now be defined as the [[pullback (category theory)|pullback]] of '''true''' andalong the characteristic function χ<sub>''A''</sub>, alsoshown writtenon ''A''the =following χ<sub>''A''</sub><sup>−1</sup>(1)diagram:
'''Axiom''': Given a category '''C''' with a subobject classifier, there exists an [[isomorphism]],
[[Image:SubobjectClassifier-01.pngsvg|center|frameless|class=skin-invert]]
:y: Sub<sub>'''C'''</sub>(''X'') ≅ Hom<sub>'''C'''</sub>(X, Ω) ∀ ''X'' ∈ '''C'''
 
ThisDefined axiomthat impliesway, theχ alternativeis a morphism ''Sub''<sub>C</sub>(''S'') → Hom<sub>C</sub>(S, Ω). By definition, ofΩ is a '''subobject classifier:''' if this morphism χ is an isomorphism.
 
'''Definition''': Ω is a '''subobject classifier''' iff there is a one to one correspondence between subobjects of ''X'' and [[morphisms]] from ''X'' to Ω.
 
== Definition ==
 
For the general definition, we start with a category '''C''' that has a [[terminal object]], which we denote by 1. The object Ω of '''C''' is a ''subobject classifier'' for '''C''' if there exists a morphism
:1 → Ω
 
with the following property:
:forFor each [[monomorphism]] ''j'': ''U'' → ''X'' there is a unique morphism ''χ<sub> j</sub>'': ''X'' → Ω such that the following [[commutative diagram]]
[[Image:SubobjectClassifier-02.pngsvg|center|frameless|class=skin-invert]]
:is a [[pullback diagram]] — that—that is, ''U'' is the [[limit (category theory)|limit]] of the diagram:
[[Image:SubobjectClassifier-03.pngsvg|center|frameless|class=skin-invert]]
 
The morphism ''χ<sub> j</sub>'' is then called the '''classifying morphism''' for the subobject represented by ''j''.
Line 42 ⟶ 36:
== Further examples ==
 
=== Sheaves of sets ===
Every [[elementary topos]], defined as a category with finite [[Limit (category theory)|limits]] and [[power object]]s, necessarily has a subobject classifier.<ref>Pedicchio & Tholen (2004) p.8</ref> For the topos of [[sheaf (mathematics)|sheaves]] of sets on a [[topological space]] ''X'', it can be described in these terms: For any [[open set]] ''U'' of ''X'', <math>\Omega(U)</math> is the set of all open subsets of ''U''. Roughly speaking an assertion inside this topos is variably true or false, and its truth value from the viewpoint of an open subset ''U'' is the open subset of ''U'' where the assertion is true.
The category of [[sheaf (mathematics)|sheaves]] of sets on a [[topological space]] ''X'' has a subobject classifier Ω which can be described as follows: For any [[open set]] ''U'' of ''X'', Ω(''U'') is the set of all open subsets of ''U''. The terminal object is the sheaf 1 which assigns the [[Singleton (mathematics)|singleton]] {*} to every open set ''U'' of ''X.'' The morphism η:1 → Ω is given by the family of maps η<sub>''U''</sub> : 1(''U'') → Ω(''U'') defined by η<sub>''U''</sub>(*)=''U'' for every open set ''U'' of ''X''. Given a sheaf ''F'' on ''X'' and a sub-sheaf ''j'': ''G'' → ''F'', the classifying morphism ''χ<sub> j</sub>'' : ''F'' → Ω is given by the family of maps ''χ<sub> j,U</sub>'' : ''F''(''U'') → Ω(''U''), where ''χ<sub> j,U</sub>''(''x'') is the union of all open sets ''V'' of ''U'' such that the restriction of ''x'' to ''V'' (in the sense of sheaves) is contained in ''j<sub>V</sub>''(''G''(''V'')).
For a small category <math>C</math>, the '''subobject classifer''' in the '''topos of presheaves''' <math>\mathrm{Set}^{C^{op}}</math> is given as follows. For any <math>c \in C</math>, <math>\Omega(c)</math> is the set of [[Sieve (category theory)|sieves]] on <math>c</math>.
 
Roughly speaking an assertion inside this topos is variably true or false, and its truth value from the viewpoint of an open subset ''U'' is the open subset of ''U'' where the assertion is true.
== References ==
 
=== Presheaves ===
<references />
Given a small category <math>C</math>, the category of [[presheaves]] <math>\mathrm{Set}^{C^{op}}</math> (i.e. the [[functor category]] consisting of all contravariant functors from <math>C</math> to <math>\mathrm{Set}</math>) has a subobject classifer given by the functor sending any <math>c \in C</math> to the set of [[Sieve (category theory)|sieves]] on <math>c</math>. The classifying morphisms are constructed quite similarly to the ones in the sheaves-of-sets example above.
 
=== Elementary topoi ===
Both examples above are subsumed by the following general fact: every [[elementary topos]], defined as a category with finite [[Limit (category theory)|limits]] and [[power object]]s, necessarily has a subobject classifier.<ref>Pedicchio & Tholen (2004) p.8</ref> The two examples above are [[Topos|Grothendieck topoi]], and every Grothendieck topos is an elementary topos.
 
== Related concepts ==
A [[quasitopos]] has an object that is almost a subobject classifier; it only classifies strong subobjects.
 
== Notes ==
 
{{Reflist}}
 
== References ==
*{{cite book
| last = Artin
| first = Michael
| author-link = Michael Artin |author2=Alexander Grothendieck |author2-link=Alexander Grothendieck |author3=Jean-Louis Verdier |author3-link=Jean-Louis Verdier | title = Séminaire de Géometrie Algébrique IV
| authorlink = Michael Artin
| coauthors = [[Alexander Grothendieck]], [[Jean-Louis Verdier]]
| title = Séminaire de Géometrie Algébrique IV
| publisher = [[Springer-Verlag]]
| year = 1964
| isbn = }}
*{{cite book
| last = Barr
Line 73 ⟶ 77:
| ___location = Oxford
| year = 1988
| isbn = }}
*{{cite book
| last = Goldblatt
| first = Robert
| title = Topoi: The Categorial Analysis of Logic
| publisher = [[North-Holland Publishing Company|North-Holland]], Reprinted by Dover Publications, Inc (2006)
| year = 1983
| isbn = 0-444-85207-7
| url = httphttps://historical.library.cornell.edu/cgi-bin/cul.math/docviewer?did=Gold010&id=3}}
*{{cite book
| last = Johnstone
Line 89 ⟶ 93:
| ___location = Oxford
| year = 2002
| isbn = }}
*{{cite book
| last = Johnstone
| first = Peter
| title = Topos Theory
| url = https://archive.org/details/topostheory0000john
| url-access = registration
| publisher = [[Academic Press]]
| year = 1977
| isbn = 0-12-387850-0}}
* {{cite book | last=Mac Lane | first=Saunders | authorlinkauthor-link=Saunders Mac Lane | title=[[Categories for the Working Mathematician]] | edition=2nd | series=[[Graduate Texts in Mathematics]] | volume=5 | ___location=New York, NY | publisher=[[Springer-Verlag]] | year=1998 | isbn=0-387-98403-8 | zbl=0906.18001 }}
*{{cite book
| last = Mac Lane
| first = Saunders
| authorlinkauthor-link = Saunders Mac Lane
|author2=Ieke Moerdijk
| title = Sheaves in Geometry and Logic: a First Introduction to Topos Theory
| publisher = [[Springer-Verlag]]
| ___location =
| year = 1992
| isbn = 0-387-97710-4}}
Line 111 ⟶ 116:
| last = McLarty
| first = Colin
| authorlinkauthor-link=Colin McLarty
| title = Elementary Categories, Elementary Toposes
| publisher = [[Oxford University Press]]
Line 117 ⟶ 122:
| year = 1992
| isbn = 0-19-853392-6}}
* {{cite book | editor1-last=Pedicchio | editor1-first=Maria Cristina|editor1-link=M. Cristina Pedicchio | editor2-last=Tholen | editor2-first=Walter | title=Categorical foundations. Special topics in order, topology, algebra, and sheaf theory | series=Encyclopedia of Mathematics and Its Applications | volume=97 | ___location=Cambridge | publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] | year=2004 | isbn=0-521-83414-7 | zbl=1034.18001 }}
*{{cite book
| last = Taylor