Evolutionarily stable strategy and User talk:76.102.153.133: Difference between pages

(Difference between pages)
Content deleted Content added
References: +1 review & alphabetize
 
No edit summary
 
Line 1:
{{{icon|[[Image:Stop hand nuvola.svg|30px]] }}}This is the '''only warning''' you will receive for your disruptive edits. If you [[Wikipedia:Vandalism|vandalize]] Wikipedia again{{{{{subst|}}}#if:{{{1|}}}|, as you did to [[:{{{1}}}]]}}, you will be [[Wikipedia:Blocking policy|blocked]] from editing. {{{{{subst|}}}#if:{{{2|}}}|{{{2}}}|}}<!-- Template:uw-vandalism4im -->
{{Infobox equilibrium|
name=Evolutionarily stable strategy|
subsetof=[[Nash equilibrium]]|
intersectwith=[[Subgame perfect equilibrium]], [[Trembling hand perfect equilibrium]], [[Perfect Bayesian equilibrium]]|
discoverer=[[John Maynard Smith]] and [[George R. Price]]|
example=[[Hawk-dove]] (aka [[Game of chicken]])|
usedfor=[[Biology|Biological modeling]] and [[Evolutionary game theory]]}}
 
{{{icon|[[Image:Stop hand nuvola.svg|30px]] }}}This is your '''last warning'''. The next time you [[Wikipedia:Vandalism|vandalize]] Wikipedia{{{{{subst|}}}#if:{{{1|}}}|, as you did to [[:{{{1}}}]]}}, you will be [[Wikipedia:Blocking policy|blocked]] from editing. {{{{{subst|}}}#if:{{{2|}}}|{{{2}}}|}}<!-- Template:uw-vandalism4 -->
In [[game theory]], an '''evolutionarily stable strategy''' (or ESS; also evolutionary stable strategy) is a [[strategy (game theory)|strategy]] which if adopted by a [[population genetics|population]] cannot be invaded by any competing alternative strategy. The concept is an [[equilibrium refinement]] to a [[Nash equilibrium]]. The difference between a Nash equilibrium and an ESS is that a Nash equilibrium may sometimes exist due to the assumption that [[Homo economicus|rational foresight]] prevents players from playing an alternative strategy with no short term cost, but which will eventually be beaten by a third strategy. An ESS is defined to exclude such equilibria, and assumes only that [[natural selection]] prevent players from using strategies which lead to lower payoffs.
 
{{{icon|[[Image:Stop hand nuvola.svg|30px]] }}}This is the '''only warning''' you will receive for your disruptive edits. If you [[Wikipedia:Vandalism|vandalize]] Wikipedia again{{{{{subst|}}}#if:{{{1|}}}|, as you did to [[:{{{1}}}]]}}, you will be [[Wikipedia:Blocking policy|blocked]] from editing. {{{{{subst|}}}#if:{{{2|}}}|{{{2}}}|}}<!-- Template:uw-vandalism4im -->
The definition of an ESS was introduced by [[John Maynard Smith]] and [[George R. Price]] in 1973 (a full account is given by Maynard Smith's 1982 book ''[[Evolution and the Theory of Games]]'') based on [[W.D. Hamilton]]'s (1967) concept of an [[unbeatable strategy]] in [[sex ratio]]s. The idea can be traced back to [[Ronald Fisher]] (1930) and [[Charles Darwin]] (1859), (see Edwards, 1998).
 
== Nash equilibria and ESS ==
A [[Nash equilibrium]] is a strategy in a game such that if all players adopt it, no player will benefit by switching to play any alternative strategy. If a player choosing strategy ''J'' in a population where all other players play strategy ''I'' receives a payoff of E(''J'',''I''), then strategy ''I'' is a Nash equilibrium if,
:E(''I'',''I'') ≥ E(''J'',''I'')
This equilibrium definition allows for the possibility that strategy ''J'' is a neutral alternative to ''I'' (it scores equally, but not better). A Nash equilibrium is presumed to be stable even if ''J'' scores equally, on the assumption that players do not play ''J''
 
[[John Maynard Smith|Maynard Smith]] and [[George R. Price|Price]] specify (Maynard Smith & Price, 1973; [[Evolution and the Theory of Games|Maynard Smith 1982]]) two conditions for a strategy ''I'' to be an ESS. Either
 
# E(''I'',''I'') > E(''J'',''I''), or
# E(''I'',''I'') = E(''J'',''I'') and E(''I'',''J'') > E(''J'',''J'')
 
must be true for all ''I'' ≠ ''J'', where E(''I'',''J'') is the expected payoff to strategy ''I'' when playing against strategy ''J''.
 
The first condition is sometimes called a 'strict Nash' equilibrium (Harsanyi, 1973), the second is sometimes referred to as 'Maynard Smith's second condition'.
 
There is also an alternative definition of ESS which, though it maintains functional equivalence, places a different emphasis on the role of the Nash equilibrium concept in the ESS concept. Following the terminology given in the first definition above, we have (adapted from Thomas, 1985):
 
# E(''I'',''I'') ≥ E(''J'',''I''), and
# E(''I'',''J'') > E(''J'',''J'')
 
In this formulation, the first condition specifies that the strategy be a Nash equilibrium, and the second specifies that Maynard Smith's second condition be met. Note that despite the difference in formulation, the two definitions are actually equivalent.
 
One advantage to this change is that the role of the Nash equilibrium in the ESS is more clearly highlighted. It also allows for a natural definition of other concepts like a [[weak ESS]] or an [[evolutionarily stable set]] (Thomas, 1985).
 
=== An example ===
Consider the following [[payoff matrix]], describing a coordination game such as the [[Stag hunt]], or [[Battle of the sexes (game theory)|Battle of the sexes]]:
 
{| border="1" cellpadding="4" cellspacing="0"
|-
|
! A
! B
|-
! A
| 1, 1
| 0, 0
|-
! B
| 0, 0
| 1, 1
|}
 
Both strategies A and B are ESS, since a B player cannot invade a population of A players nor can an A player invade a population of B players. Here the two pure strategy Nash equilibria correspond to the two ESS. In this second game, which also has two pure strategy Nash equilibria, only one corresponds to an ESS:
 
{| border="1" cellpadding="4" cellspacing="0"
|-
|
! C
! D
|-
! C
| 1, 1
| 0, 0
|-
! D
| 0, 0
| 0, 0
|}
 
Here (D, D) is a Nash equilibrium (since neither player will do better by unilaterally deviating), but it is not an ESS. Consider a C player introduced into a population of D players. The C player does equally well against the population (she scores 0), however the C player does better against herself (she scores 1) than the population does against the C player. Thus, the C player can invade the population of D players.
 
Even if a game has pure strategy Nash equilibria, it might be the case that none of the strategies are ESS. Consider the following example (known as [[Game of chicken|Chicken]]):
 
{| border="1" cellpadding="4" cellspacing="0"
|-
|
! E
! F
|-
! E
| 0, 0
| -1, +1
|-
! F
| +1, -1
| -20, -20
|}
 
There are two pure strategy Nash equilibria in this game (E, F) and (F, E). However, in the absence of an [[uncorrelated asymmetry]]), neither F nor E are ESSes. A third Nash equilibrium exists, a mixed strategy, which is an ESS for this game (see [[Hawk-dove game]] and [[Best response]] for explanation).
 
== ESS vs. Evolutionarily Stable State ==
:An '''ESS''' or '''evolutionarily stable strategy''' is a strategy such that, if all the members of a population adopt it, no mutant strategy can invade. --[[John Maynard Smith|Maynard Smith]] (1982).
 
:A population is said to be in an '''evolutionarily stable state''' if its genetic composition is restored by selection after a disturbance, provided the disturbance is not too large. Such a population can be genetically monomorphic or polymorphic. --[[John Maynard Smith|Maynard Smith]] (1982).
 
An ESS is a strategy with the property that, once virtually all members of the population use it, then no 'rational' alternative exists. An [[evolutionarily stable state]] is a dynamical property of a population to return to using a strategy, or mix of strategies, if it is perturbed from that strategy, or mix of strategies. The former concept fits within classical [[game theory]], whereas the latter is a [[population genetics]], [[dynamical system]], or [[evolutionary game theory]] concept.
 
== Prisoner's dilemma and ESS ==
Consider a large population of people who, in the iterated [[prisoner's dilemma]], always play [[Tit for Tat]] in transactions with each other. (Since almost any transaction requires trust, most transactions can be modelled with the ''prisoner's dilemma''.) If the entire population plays the ''Tit-for-Tat'' strategy, and a group of newcomers enter the population who prefer the ''Always Defect'' strategy (i.e. they try to cheat everyone they meet), the ''Tit-for-Tat'' strategy will prove more successful, and the ''defectors'' will be converted or lose out. ''Tit for Tat'' is therefore an ESS, ''with respect to these two strategies''. On the other hand, an island of ''Always Defect'' players will be stable against the invasion of a few ''Tit-for-Tat'' players, but not against a large number of them. (see [[Robert Axelrod]]'s [[The Evolution of Cooperation]], or more briefly [http://www.urticator.net/essay/2/217.html here]).
 
== ESS and human behavior ==
The recent, controversial sciences of [[sociobiology]] and now [[evolutionary psychology]] attempt to explain animal and human behavior and social structures, largely in terms of evolutionarily stable strategies. For example, in one [http://www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/OldArchive/bbs.mealey.html well-known 1995 paper] by Linda Mealey, [[sociopathy]] (chronic antisocial/criminal behavior) is explained as a combination of two such strategies.
 
Although ESS were originally considered as stable states for biological evolution, it need not be limited to such contexts. In fact, ESS are stable states for a large class of [[adaptive dynamics]]. As a result ESS are used to explain human behavior without presuming that the behavior is necessarily determined by [[gene]]s.
 
== References ==
* [[Robert Axelrod]] (1984) ''[[The Evolution of Cooperation]]'' ISBN 0465021212
* [[Charles Darwin]] (1859). ''[[On the Origin of Species]]''
* [[Ronald Fisher]] ''[[The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection]]''. Clarendon Press, Oxford.
* [[W.D. Hamilton]] (1967) "Extraordinary sex ratios." ''[[Science (journal)|Science]]''
* [[John Harsanyi|Harsanyi, J]] (1973) "Oddness of the number of equilibrium points: a new proof". Int. J. Game Theory. 2: 235-250.
* Hines, WGS (1987) Evolutionary stable strategies: a review of basic theory. ''Theoretical Population Biology'' '''31''': 195-272.
* [[John Maynard Smith]] and [[George R. Price]] (1973). "The logic of animal conflict." ''[[Nature (journal)|Nature]]''
* [[John Maynard Smith]]. (1982) ''[[Evolution and the Theory of Games]]''. ISBN 0521288843
* [[Bernhard Thomas|Thomas, B]] (1985) "On evolutionarily stable sets." J. Math. Biology 22: 105-115.
 
==External links==
*[http://www.bbsonline.org/Preprints/OldArchive/bbs.mealey.html ''The Sociobiology of Sociopathy'', Mealey, 1995]
 
{{Game_theory}}
 
[[Category:Game theory]]
[[Category:evolutionary biology]]
 
[[de:Evolutionär stabile Strategie]]
[[fr:Stratégie évolutionnairement stable]]
[[ja:進化的に安定な戦略]]