Content deleted Content added
mNo edit summary Tags: Mobile edit Mobile app edit iOS app edit |
→2) 'Bang for buck': Fixed awkward wording Tags: Mobile edit Mobile web edit |
||
(16 intermediate revisions by 15 users not shown) | |||
Line 2:
{{For|a less technical introduction|Utility}}
{{Multiple issues|
{{More footnotes needed|date=August 2010}}
{{more citations needed|date=March 2011}}
}}
Utility maximization was first developed by utilitarian philosophers [[Jeremy Bentham]] and [[John
Utility maximization is an important concept in consumer theory as it shows how consumers decide to allocate their income. Because consumers are modelled as being [[Rational choice theory|rational]], they seek to extract the most benefit for themselves. However, due to [[bounded rationality]] and other biases, consumers sometimes pick bundles that do not necessarily maximize their utility. The utility maximization bundle of the consumer is also not set and can change over time depending on their individual preferences of goods, price changes and increases or decreases in income.
==Basic setup==
Line 19:
=== 1) Walras's Law ===
[[Walras's law]] states that if a consumers preferences are complete, monotone and transitive then the optimal demand will lie on the [[Budget constraint|budget line]].<ref>{{Cite book|last=Levin|first=Jonothan|title=Consumer theory|publisher=Stanford university|year=2004|pages=4–6}}</ref>
==== Preferences of the consumer ====
Line 37:
For a preference relation to be [[Monotone preferences|monotone]] increasing the quantity of both goods should make the consumer strictly better off (increase their utility), and increasing the quantity of one good holding the other quantity constant should not make the consumer worse off (same utility).
The preference <math>\succcurlyeq</math> is monotone if
1)<math>(x+\epsilon, y)\succcurlyeq(x,y)</math>
Line 49:
=== 2) 'Bang for buck' ===
[[Bang for the buck|Bang for buck]] is a
<math> MU_x/p_x = MU_y/p_y</math>
Line 77:
<math>p \in \mathbb{R}^n_+ \ ,</math>
and that the consumer's income is <math>
<math>B(p, I) = \{x \in \mathbb{R}^n_+ | \mathbb{\Sigma}^n_{i=1} p_i x_i \leq I\} \ ,</math>
Line 87:
:<math>u : \mathbb{R}^n_+ \rightarrow \mathbb{R}_+ \ .</math>
Then the consumer's optimal choice <math>x(p,
<math>x(p, I) = \{x \in B(p,I)| U(x) \geq U(y) \forall y \in B(p,I)\}</math>
Line 95:
If ''u'' is continuous and no commodities are free of charge, then <math>x(p,I)</math> exists,<ref>{{Cite book|title=Choice, preference and Utility|publisher=Princeton university press|year=n.d.|pages=14}}</ref> but it is not necessarily unique. If the preferences of the consumer are complete, transitive and strictly convex then the demand of the consumer contains a unique maximiser for all values of the price and wealth parameters. If this is satisfied then <math>x(p,I)</math> is called the [[Marshallian demand function]]. Otherwise, <math>x(p,I)</math> is set-valued and it is called the [[Marshallian demand correspondence]].
== Utility maximisation of perfect
U = min {x, y}
[[File:Utility_maximisation_of_a_minimum_function.png|thumb|Figure 3: This shows the utility maximisation problem with a minimum utility function.]]
For a minimum function with goods that are [[Complementary good|perfect
== Utility maximisation of perfect substitutes ==
U =
For a utility function with [[Substitute good|perfect substitutes]], the utility maximising bundle can be found by differentiation or simply by inspection. Suppose a consumer finds listening to [[Australia|Australian]] rock bands [[AC/DC]] and [[Tame Impala]] perfect substitutes. This means that they are happy to spend all afternoon listening to only AC/DC, or only Tame Impala, or three-quarters AC/DC and one-quarter Tame Impala, or any combination of the two bands in any amount. Therefore, the consumer's optimal choice is determined entirely by the relative prices of listening to the two artists. If attending a Tame Impala concert is cheaper than attending the AC/DC concert, the consumer chooses to attend the Tame Impala concert, and vice versa. If the two concert prices are the same, the consumer is completely indifferent and may flip a coin to decide. To see this mathematically, differentiate the utility function to find that the [[marginal rate of substitution|MRS]] is constant - this is the technical meaning of perfect substitutes. As a result of this, the solution to the consumer's constrained maximization problem will not (generally) be an interior solution, and as such one must check the utility level in the boundary cases (spend entire budget on good x, spend entire budget on good y) to see which is the solution. The special case is when the (constant) MRS equals the price ratio (for example, both goods have the same price, and same coefficients in the utility function). In this case, any combination of the two goods is a solution to the consumer problem.
== Reaction to changes in prices ==
For a given level of real wealth, only relative prices matter to consumers, not absolute prices. If consumers reacted to changes in nominal prices and nominal wealth even if relative prices and real wealth remained unchanged, this would be an effect called [[money illusion]]. The mathematical first order conditions for a maximum of the consumer problem guarantee that the demand for each good is homogeneous of degree zero jointly in nominal prices and nominal wealth, so there is no money illusion.
When the prices of goods change, the optimal consumption of these goods will depend on the substitution and income effects. The [[substitution effect]] says that if the demand for both goods is
The income effect occurs when the change in prices of goods cause a change in income. If the price of one good rises, then income is decreased (more costly than before to consume the same bundle), the same goes if the price of a good falls, income is increased (cheeper to consume the same bundle, they can therefore consume more of their desired combination of goods).<ref name=":1" />
Line 116 ⟶ 115:
== Reaction to changes in income ==
[[File:Optimal_bundle_reaction_to_changes_in_income.png|thumb|232x232px|Figure 5: This shows how the optimal bundle of a consumer changes when their income is increased.]]
If the consumers income is increased their budget line is shifted outwards
== Bounded rationality ==
Line 124 ⟶ 123:
* The [[satisficing]] heuristic is when a consumer defines an aspiration level and looks until they find an option that satisfies this, they will deem this option good enough and stop looking.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Wheeler|first=Gregory|title=bounded rationality|publisher=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|year=2018}}</ref>
* [[Heuristics in judgment and decision-making|Elimination by aspects]] is defining a level for each aspect of a product they want and eliminating all other options that
* The [[mental accounting]] heuristic: In this strategy it is seen that people often assign subjective values to their money depending on their preferences for different things. A person will develop mental accounts for different expenses, allocate their budget within these, then try to maximise their utility within each account.<ref>{{Cite web|date=2021|title=Why do we think less about some purchases than others?|url=https://thedecisionlab.com/biases/mental-accounting/
== Related concepts ==
Line 133 ⟶ 132:
==See also==
*[[Welfare maximization]]
*[[Profit maximization]]
*[[Choice modelling]]
*[[Expenditure minimization problem|Expenditure minimisation problem]]
|