Countable set: Difference between revisions

Content deleted Content added
m Fixed a linguistic issue.
Formal overview: Fix grammar.
 
(23 intermediate revisions by 14 users not shown)
Line 11:
 
==A note on terminology <span class="anchor" id="Terminology"></span>==
Although the terms "countable" and "countably infinite" as defined here are quite common, the terminology is not universal.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Manetti |first1=Marco |title=Topology |date=19 June 2015 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3-319-16958-3 |page=26 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=89zyCQAAQBAJ&pg=PA26 |language=en}}</ref> An alternative style uses ''countable'' to mean what is here called countably infinite, and ''at most countable'' to mean what is here called countable.<ref name="Rudin">{{Harvard citation no brackets|Rudin|1976|loc=Chapter 2}}</ref><ref>{{harvnb|Tao|2016|p=181}}</ref> To avoid ambiguity, one may limit oneself to the terms "at most countable" and "countably infinite", although with respect to [[concision]] this is the worst of both worlds.{{cn|date=September 2021}} The reader is advised to check the definition in use when encountering the term "countable" in the literature.
 
The terms ''enumerable''<ref>{{Harvard citation no brackets|Kamke|1950|page=2}}</ref> and '''denumerable'''<ref name="Lang">{{Harvard citation no brackets|Lang|1993|loc=§2 of Chapter I}}</ref><ref name="Apostol">{{Harvard citation no brackets|Apostol|1969|loc=Chapter 1.14|p=23}}</ref> may also be used, e.g. referring to countable and countably infinite respectively,<ref>{{cite book |last1=Thierry |first1=Vialar |title=Handbook of Mathematics |date=4 April 2017 |publisher=BoD - Books on Demand |isbn=978-2-9551990-1-5 |page=24 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=RkepDgAAQBAJ&pg=PA24 |language=en}}</ref> but as definitions vary theand readercare is onceneeded againrespecting advisedthe todifference checkwith the[[Recursively definitionenumerable inlanguage|recursively useenumerable]].<ref>{{cite book |last1=Mukherjee |first1=Subir Kumar |title=First Course in Real Analysis |date=2009 |publisher=Academic Publishers |isbn=978-81-89781-90-3 |page=22 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=n5AhsN5UQ8IC&pg=PA22 |language=en}}</ref>
 
==Definition==
 
*A set <math>S</math> is ''countable.<ref'' name="Lang"/>if:
The most concise definition is in terms of [[cardinality]]. A set <math>S</math> is ''countable'' if its cardinality <math>|S|</math> is less than or equal to <math>\aleph_0</math> ([[aleph-null]]), the cardinality of the set of [[natural numbers]] <math>\N = \{ 0, 1, 2, 3, \ldots \}</math>. A set <math>S</math> is ''countably [[infinite set|infinite]]'' if <math>|S| = \aleph_0</math>. A set is ''[[uncountable]]'' if it is not countable, i.e. its cardinality is greater than <math>\aleph_0</math>; the reader is referred to [[Uncountable set]] for further discussion.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Yaqub |first1=Aladdin M. |title=An Introduction to Metalogic |date=24 October 2014 |publisher=Broadview Press |isbn=978-1-4604-0244-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=cyljCAAAQBAJ&pg=PT187 |language=en}}</ref>
* Its [[cardinality]] <math>|S|</math> is less than or equal to <math>\aleph_0</math> ([[aleph-null]]), the cardinality of the set of [[natural numbers]] <math>\N</math>.<ref name=Yaqub/>
 
* There exists an [[injective function]] from {{mvar|<math>S}}</math> to <math>\N</math>.<ref name=Singh>{{cite book |last1=Singh |first1=Tej Bahadur |title=Introduction to Topology |date=17 May 2019 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-981-13-6954-4 |page=422 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=UQiZDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA422 |language=en}}</ref><ref name=Katzourakis>{{cite book |last1=Katzourakis |first1=Nikolaos |last2=Varvaruca |first2=Eugen |title=An Illustrative Introduction to Modern Analysis |date=2 January 2018 |publisher=CRC Press |isbn=978-1-351-76532-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=jBFFDwAAQBAJ&pg=PT15 |language=en}}</ref>
For every set <math>S</math>, the following propositions are equivalent:
* <math>S</math> is countable.<ref name="Lang"/>
* There exists an [[injective function]] from {{mvar|S}} to <math>\N</math>.<ref name=Singh>{{cite book |last1=Singh |first1=Tej Bahadur |title=Introduction to Topology |date=17 May 2019 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-981-13-6954-4 |page=422 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=UQiZDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA422 |language=en}}</ref><ref name=Katzourakis>{{cite book |last1=Katzourakis |first1=Nikolaos |last2=Varvaruca |first2=Eugen |title=An Illustrative Introduction to Modern Analysis |date=2 January 2018 |publisher=CRC Press |isbn=978-1-351-76532-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=jBFFDwAAQBAJ&pg=PT15 |language=en}}</ref>
* <math>S</math> is empty or there exists a [[surjective function]] from <math>\N</math> to <math>S</math>.<ref name=Katzourakis/>
* There exists a [[bijective]] mapping between <math>S</math> and a subset of <math>\N</math>.<ref>{{harvnb|Halmos|1960|loc=p. 91}}</ref>
* <math>S</math> is either [[Finite set|finite]] (<math>|S|<\aleph_0</math>) or countably infinite.<ref>{{Cite web|lastname=Weisstein|first=Eric W.|title=Countable Set |url=https:"Lang"//mathworld.wolfram.com/CountableSet.html|access-date=2020-09-06|website=mathworld.wolfram.com|language=en}}</ref>
All of these definitions are equivalent.
 
A set <math>S</math> is ''countably [[infinite set|infinite]]'' if:
Similarly, the following propositions are equivalent:
* Its cardinality <math>|S|</math> is countablyexactly infinite<math>\aleph_0</math>.<ref name=Yaqub/>
* There is an injective and surjective (and therefore [[bijection|bijective]]) mapping between <math>S</math> and <math>\N</math>.
* <math>S</math> has a [[One-one correspondence|one-to-one correspondence]] with <math>\N</math>.<ref>{{harvnb|Kamke|1950|loc=p. 2}}</ref>
* The elements of <math>S</math> can be arranged in an infinite sequence <math>a_0, a_1, a_2, \ldots</math>, where <math>a_i</math> is distinct from <math>a_j</math> for <math>i\neq j</math> and every element of <math>S</math> is listed.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Dlab |first1=Vlastimil |last2=Williams |first2=Kenneth S. |title=Invitation To Algebra: A Resource Compendium For Teachers, Advanced Undergraduate Students And Graduate Students In Mathematics |date=9 June 2020 |publisher=World Scientific |isbn=978-981-12-1999-3 |page=8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=l9rrDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA8 |language=en}}</ref><ref>{{harvnb|Tao|2016|p=182}}</ref>
 
The most concise definition is in terms of [[cardinality]]. A set <math>S</math> is ''countable'' if its cardinality <math>|S|</math> is less than or equal to <math>\aleph_0</math> ([[aleph-null]]), the cardinality of the set of [[natural numbers]] <math>\N = \{ 0, 1, 2, 3, \ldots \}</math>. A set <math>S</math> is ''countably [[infinite set|infinite]]'' if <math>|S| = \aleph_0</math>. A set is ''[[uncountable]]'' if it is not countable, i.e. its cardinality is greater than <math>\aleph_0</math>; the reader is referred to [[Uncountable set]] for further discussion.<ref name=Yaqub>{{cite book |last1=Yaqub |first1=Aladdin M. |title=An Introduction to Metalogic |date=24 October 2014 |publisher=Broadview Press |isbn=978-1-4604-0244-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=cyljCAAAQBAJ&pg=PT187 |language=en}}</ref>
 
==History==
Line 36 ⟶ 37:
 
==Introduction==
A ''[[Set (mathematics)|set]]'' is a collection of ''elements'', and may be described in many ways. One way is simply to list all of its elements; for example, the set consisting of the integers 3, 4, and 5 may be denoted <math>\{3, 4, 5\}</math>, called roster form.<ref>{{Cite web|date=2021-05-09|title=What Are Sets and Roster Form?|url=https://www.expii.com/t/what-are-sets-and-roster-form-4300| url-status=live|website=expii|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200918224155/https://www.expii.com/t/what-are-sets-and-roster-form-4300 |archive-date=2020-09-18 }}</ref> This is only effective for small sets, however; for larger sets, this would be time-consuming and error-prone. Instead of listing every single element, sometimes an ellipsis ("...") is used to represent many elements between the starting element and the end element in a set, if the writer believes that the reader can easily guess what ... represents; for example, <math>\{1, 2, 3, ...\dots, 100\}</math> presumably denotes the set of [[integer]]s from 1 to 100. Even in this case, however, it is still ''possible'' to list all the elements, because the number of elements in the set is finite. If we number the elements of the set 1, 2, and so on, up to <math>n</math>, this gives us the usual definition of "sets of size <math>n</math>".
 
[[File:Aplicación 2 inyectiva sobreyectiva02.svg|thumb|x100px|Bijective mapping from integer to even numbers]]
Some sets are ''infinite''; these sets have more than <math>n</math> elements where <math>n</math> is any integer that can be specified. (No matter how large the specified integer <math>n</math> is, such as <math>n=10^{1000}</math>, infinite sets have more than <math>n</math> elements.) For example, the set of natural numbers, denotable by <math>\{0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ...\dots\}</math>,{{efn|name=ZeroN|Since there is an obvious [[bijection]] between <math>\N</math> and <math>\N^*=\{1,2,3,\dots\}</math>, it makes no difference whether one considers 0 a natural number or not. In any case, this article follows [[ISO 31-11]] and the standard convention in [[mathematical logic]], which takes 0 as a natural number.}} has infinitely many elements, and we cannot use any natural number to give its size. It might seem natural to divide the sets into different classes: put all the sets containing one element together; all the sets containing two elements together; ...; finally, put together all infinite sets and consider them as having the same size. This view works well for countably infinite sets and was the prevailing assumption before Georg Cantor's work. For example, there are infinitely many odd integers, infinitely many even integers, and also infinitely many integers overall. We can consider all these sets to have the same "size" because we can arrange things such that, for every integer, there is a distinct even integer:
<math display="block">\ldots \, -\! 2\! \rightarrow \! - \! 4, \, -\! 1\! \rightarrow \! - \! 2, \, 0\! \rightarrow \! 0, \, 1\! \rightarrow \! 2, \, 2\! \rightarrow \! 4 \, \cdots</math>
or, more generally, <math>n \rightarrow 2n</math> (see picture). What we have done here is arrange the integers and the even integers into a ''one-to-one correspondence'' (or ''[[bijection]]''), which is a [[function (mathematics)|function]] that maps between two sets such that each element of each set corresponds to a single element in the other set. This mathematical notion of "size", cardinality, is that two sets are of the same size if and only if there is a bijection between them. We call all sets that are in one-to-one correspondence with the integers ''countably infinite'' and say they have cardinality <math>\aleph_0</math>.
Line 48 ⟶ 49:
 
By definition, a set <math>S</math> is ''countable'' if there exists a [[bijection]] between <math>S</math> and a subset of the [[natural numbers]] <math>\N=\{0,1,2,\dots\}</math>. For example, define the correspondence
<math display=block>
{{block indent|em=1.5|text=''a'' ↔ 1, ''b'' ↔ 2, ''c'' ↔ 3}}
a \leftrightarrow 1,\ b \leftrightarrow 2,\ c \leftrightarrow 3
Since every element of <math>S=\{a,b,c\}</math> is paired with ''precisely one'' element of <math>\{1,2,3\}</math>, ''and'' vice versa, this defines a bijection, and shows that <math>S</math> is countable. Similarly we can show all finite sets are countable.
</math>
 
Since every element of <math>S=\{a,b,c\}</math> is paired with ''precisely one'' element of <math>\{1,2,3\}</math>, ''and'' vice versa, this defines a bijection, and shows that <math>S</math> is countable. Similarly we can show all finite sets areto be countable.
As for the case of infinite sets, a set <math>S</math> is countably infinite if there is a [[bijection]] between <math>S</math> and all of <math>\N</math>. As examples, consider the sets <math>A=\{1,2,3,\dots\}</math>, the set of positive [[integer]]s, and <math>B=\{0,2,4,6,\dots\}</math>, the set of even integers. We can show these sets are countably infinite by exhibiting a bijection to the natural numbers. This can be achieved using the assignments ''n'' ↔ ''n+1'' and ''n'' ↔ 2''n'', so that
{{block indent|em=1.5|text=0 ↔ 1, 1 ↔ 2, 2 ↔ 3, 3 ↔ 4, 4 ↔ 5, ....}}
{{block indent|em=1.5|text=0 ↔ 0, 1 ↔ 2, 2 ↔ 4, 3 ↔ 6, 4 ↔ 8, ....}}
 
As for the case of infinite sets, a set <math>S</math> is countably infinite if there is a [[bijection]] between <math>S</math> and all of <math>\N</math>. As examples, consider the sets <math>A=\{1,2,3,\dots\}</math>, the set of positive [[integer]]s, and <math>B=\{0,2,4,6,\dots\}</math>, the set of even integers. We can show these sets are countably infinite by exhibiting a bijection to the natural numbers. This can be achieved using the assignments ''<math>n'' \leftrightarrow ''n+1''</math> and ''<math>n'' \leftrightarrow 2''n''2n</math>, so that
<math display=block>\begin{matrix}
0 \leftrightarrow 1, & 1 \leftrightarrow 2, & 2 \leftrightarrow 3, & 3 \leftrightarrow 4, & 4 \leftrightarrow 5, & \ldots \\[6pt]
0 \leftrightarrow 0, & 1 \leftrightarrow 2, & 2 \leftrightarrow 4, & 3 \leftrightarrow 6, & 4 \leftrightarrow 8, & \ldots
\end{matrix}</math>
Every countably infinite set is countable, and every infinite countable set is countably infinite. Furthermore, any subset of the natural numbers is countable, and more generally:
{{math theorem | math_statement = A subset of a countable set is countable.<ref>{{harvnb|Halmos|1960|page=91}}</ref>}}
 
The set of all [[ordered pair]]s of natural numbers (the [[Cartesian product]] of two sets of natural numbers, <math>\N\times\N</math> is countably infinite, as can be seen by following a path like the one in the picture: [[File:Pairing natural.svg|thumb|300px|The [[Cantor pairing function]] assigns one natural number to each pair of natural numbers]] The resulting [[Map (mathematics)|mapping]] proceeds as follows:
<math display=block>
{{block indent|em=1.5|text=0 ↔ (0, 0), 1 ↔ (1, 0), 2 ↔ (0, 1), 3 ↔ (2, 0), 4 ↔ (1, 1), 5 ↔ (0, 2), 6 ↔ (3, 0), ....}}
0 \leftrightarrow (0, 0), 1 \leftrightarrow (1, 0), 2 \leftrightarrow (0, 1), 3 \leftrightarrow (2, 0), 4 \leftrightarrow (1, 1), 5 \leftrightarrow (0, 2), 6 \leftrightarrow (3, 0), \ldots
</math>
This mapping covers all such ordered pairs.
 
This form of triangular mapping [[recursion|recursively]] generalizes to <math>n</math>-[[tuple]]s of natural numbers, i.e., <math>(a_1,a_2,a_3,\dots,a_n)</math> where <math>a_i</math> and <math>n</math> are natural numbers, by repeatedly mapping the first two elements of an <math>n</math>-tuple to a natural number. For example, <math>(0, 2, 3)</math> can be written as <math>((0, 2), 3)</math>. Then <math>(0, 2)</math> maps to 5 so <math>((0, 2), 3)</math> maps to <math>(5, 3)</math>, then <math>(5, 3)</math> maps to 39. Since a different 2-tuple, that is a pair such as <math>(''a'', ''b'')</math>, maps to a different natural number, a difference between two n-tuples by a single element is enough to ensure the n-tuples being mapped to different natural numbers. So, an injection from the set of <math>n</math>-tuples to the set of natural numbers <math>\N</math> is proved. For the set of <math>n</math>-tuples made by the Cartesian product of finitely many different sets, each element in each tuple has the correspondence to a natural number, so every tuple can be written in natural numbers then the same logic is applied to prove the theorem.
 
{{math theorem | math_statement = The [[Cartesian product]] of finitely many countable sets is countable.<ref>{{Harvard citation no brackets|Halmos|1960|page=92}}</ref>{{efn|'''Proof:''' Observe that <math>\N\times\N</math> is countable as a consequence of the definition because the function <math>f:\N\times\N\to\N</math> given by <math>f(m,n)=2^m\cdot3^n</math> is injective.<ref>{{Harvard citation no brackets|Avelsgaard|1990|page=182}}</ref> It then follows that the Cartesian product of any two countable sets is countable, because if <math>A</math> and <math>B</math> are two countable sets there are surjections <math>f:\N\to A</math> and <math>g:\N\to B</math>. So <math>f\times g:\N\times\N\to A\times B</math>
Line 76 ⟶ 82:
Sometimes more than one mapping is useful: a set <math>A</math> to be shown as countable is one-to-one mapped (injection) to another set <math>B</math>, then <math>A</math> is proved as countable if <math>B</math> is one-to-one mapped to the set of natural numbers. For example, the set of positive [[rational number]]s can easily be one-to-one mapped to the set of natural number pairs (2-tuples) because <math>p/q</math> maps to <math>(p,q)</math>. Since the set of natural number pairs is one-to-one mapped (actually one-to-one correspondence or bijection) to the set of natural numbers as shown above, the positive rational number set is proved as countable.
 
{{math theorem | math_statement = Any finite [[union (set theory)|union]] of countable sets is countable.<ref>{{Harvard citation no brackets|Avelsgaard|1990|page=180}}</ref><ref>{{Harvard citation no brackets|Fletcher|Patty|1988|page=187}}</ref>{{efn|1='''Proof:''' If <math>A_i</math> is a countable set for each <math>i</math> in <math>I=\{1,\dots,n\}</math>, then for each <math>ni</math> there is a surjective function <math>g_i:\N\to A_i</math> and hence the function
<math display="block">G : I \times \mathbf{N} \to \bigcup_{i \in I} A_i,</math>
given by <math>G(i,m)=g_i(m)</math> is a surjection. Since <math>I\times \N</math> is countable, the union <math display="inline">\bigcup_{i \in I} A_i</math> is countable.
}}}}
 
With the foresight of knowing that there are uncountable sets, we can wonder whether or not this last result can be pushed any further. The answer is "yes" and "no", we can extend it, but we need to assume a new axiom to do so.
 
{{math theorem | math_statement = (Assuming the [[axiom of countable choice]]) The union of countably many countable sets is countable.{{efn|1='''Proof''': As in the finite case, but <math>I=\N</math> and we use the [[axiom of countable choice]] to pick for each <math>i</math> in <math>\N</math> a surjection <math>g_i</math> from the non-empty collection of surjections from <math>\N</math> to <math>A_i</math>.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Hrbacek |first1=Karel |last2=Jech |first2=Thomas |title=Introduction to Set Theory, Third Edition, Revised and Expanded |date=22 June 1999 |publisher=CRC Press |isbn=978-0-8247-7915-3 |page=141 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Er1r0n7VoSEC&pg=PA141 |language=en}}</ref> Note that since we are considering the surjection <math>G : \mathbf{N} \times \mathbf{N} \to \bigcup_{i \in I} A_i</math>, rather than an injection, there is no requirement that the sets be disjoint.}}}}
 
For example, given countable sets <math>\textbf{a},\textbf{b},\textbf{c},\dots</math>
 
[[File:Countablepath.svg|thumb|300px|Enumeration for countable number of countable sets]]
UsingFor example, given countable sets <math>\textbf{a},\textbf{b},\textbf{c},\dots</math>, we first assign each element of each set a tuple, then we assign each tuple an index using a variant of the triangular enumeration we saw above:
<math display=block>
 
\begin{array}{ c|c|c }
*''a''<sub>0</sub> maps to 0
\text{Index} & \text{Tuple} & \text {Element} \\ \hline
*''a''<sub>1</sub> maps to 1
0 & (0,0) & \textbf{a}_0 \\
*''b''<sub>0</sub> maps to 2
1 & (0,1) & \textbf{a}_1 \\
*''a''<sub>2</sub> maps to 3
2 & (1,0) & \textbf{b}_0 \\
*''b''<sub>1</sub> maps to 4
3 & (0,2) & \textbf{a}_2 \\
*''c''<sub>0</sub> maps to 5
4 & (1,1) & \textbf{b}_1 \\
*''a''<sub>3</sub> maps to 6
5 & (2,0) & \textbf{c}_0 \\
*''b''<sub>2</sub> maps to 7
6 & (0,3) & \textbf{a}_3 \\
*''c''<sub>1</sub> maps to 8
7 & (1,2) & \textbf{b}_2 \\
*''d''<sub>0</sub> maps to 9
8 & (2,1) & \textbf{c}_1 \\
*''a''<sub>4</sub> maps to 10
9 & (3,0) & \textbf{d}_0 \\
*...
10 & (0,4) & \textbf{a}_4 \\
 
\vdots & &
This only works if the sets <math>\textbf{a},\textbf{b},\textbf{c},\dots</math> are [[disjoint sets|disjoint]]. If not, then the union is even smaller and is therefore also countable by a previous theorem.
\end{array}
</math>
 
We need the [[axiom of countable choice]] to index ''all'' the sets <math>\textbf{a},\textbf{b},\textbf{c},\dots</math> simultaneously.
Line 109 ⟶ 115:
{{math theorem | math_statement = The set of all finite-length [[sequence]]s of natural numbers is countable.}}
 
This set is the union of the length-1 sequences, the length-2 sequences, the length-3 sequences, and so on, each of which is a countable set (finite Cartesian product). SoThus wethe areset talking aboutis a countable union of countable sets, which is countable by the previous theorem.
 
{{math theorem | math_statement = The set of all finite [[subset]]s of the natural numbers is countable.}}
Line 135 ⟶ 141:
* subsets of ''M'', hence countable,
* but uncountable from the point of view of ''M'',
was seen as paradoxical in the early days of set theory,; see [[Skolem's paradox]] for more.
 
The minimal standard model includes all the [[algebraic number]]s and all effectively computable [[transcendental number]]s, as well as many other kinds of numbers.
Line 164 ⟶ 170:
 
==References==
* {{Citation | first1=Tom M. | last1=Apostol | author-link=Tom M. Apostol | title=Multi-Variable Calculus and Linear Algebra with Applications | ___location=New York | publisher=John Wiley + Sons | edition=2nd | series=Calculus | volume=2 | isbn=978-0-471-00007-5 | date=June 1969 | url-access=registration | url=https://archive.org/details/calculus00apos }}
* {{citation | first=Carol|last=Avelsgaard|title=Foundations for Advanced Mathematics|year=1990|publisher=Scott, Foresman and Company|isbn=0-673-38152-8}}
* {{Citation | first = Georg | last = Cantor | title = Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre | url = http://www.digizeitschriften.de/dms/img/?PID=GDZPPN002156806 | volume = 1878 | issue = 84 | pages = 242&ndash;248 | journal = Journal für die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik | year = 1878 | doi = 10.1515/crelle-1878-18788413| s2cid = 123695365 }}