Content deleted Content added
m fixing interwikis +: gl |
→Axioms and models: models are structures, more than sets |
||
(292 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown) | |||
Line 1:
{{short description|Mathematical term; concerning axioms used to derive theorems}}
{{more footnotes|date=March 2013}}
{{Expert needed|1=Mathematics|reason=Few citations despite the degree of detail|date=January 2025}}
In [[mathematics]] and [[logic]], an '''axiomatic system''' is a [[Set (mathematics)|set]] of [[Formal language|formal statements]] (i.e. [[axiom]]s) used to logically derive other statements such as [[Lemma (mathematics)|lemma]] or [[theorem]]s. A [[formal proof|proof]] within an axiom system is a sequence of [[Deductive reasoning|deductive steps]] that establishes a news statement as a consequence of the axioms. An axiom system is called [[Completeness (logic)|complete]] with respect to a property if every formula with the property can be derived using the axioms. The more general term [[Theory (mathematical logic)|theory]] is at times used to refer to an axiomc system and all its derived theorems.
In its pure form, an axiom system is effectively a syntactic construct and does not by itself refer to (or depend on) a [[Structure (mathematical logic)|formal structure]], although axioms are often defined for that purpose. The more modern field of [[model theory]] refers to mathematical structures. The relationship between an axiom systems and the models that correspond to it is often a major issue of interest.
== Properties ==
Four typical properties of an axiom system are consistency, relative consistency, completeness and independence. An axiomatic system is said to be ''[[Consistency|consistent]]'' if it lacks [[contradiction]]. That is, it is impossible to derive both a statement and its negation from the system's axioms.<ref name=howson>A. G. Howson A Handbook of Terms Used in Algebra and Analysis, Cambridge UP, ISBN 0521084342 1972 pp 6</ref>
Consistency is a key requirement for most axiomatic systems, as the presence of contradiction would allow any statement to be proven ([[principle of explosion]]).
Relative consistency comes into play when we can not prove the consistency of an axion system. However, in some cases we can show that an axion system A is consistent if another
axiom set B is consistent.<ref name=howson />
In an axiomatic system, an axiom is called ''[[Independence (mathematical logic)|independent]]'' if it cannot be proven or disproven from other axioms in the system. A system is called independent if each of its underlying axioms is independent.<ref name=howson /> Unlike consistency, in many cases independence is not a necessary requirement for a functioning axiomatic system — though it is usually sought after to minimize the number of axioms in the system.
An axiomatic system is called ''[[Completeness (logic)|complete]]'' if for every statement, either itself or its negation is derivable from the system's axioms, i.e. every statement can be proven true or false by using the axioms.<ref name=howson /><ref>{{Cite web|url=http://mathworld.wolfram.com/CompleteAxiomaticTheory.html|title=Complete Axiomatic Theory|last=Weisstein|first=Eric W.|website=mathworld.wolfram.com|language=en|access-date=2019-10-31}}</ref> However, note that in some cases it may be [[Undecidable problem|undecidible]] if a statement can be proven or not.
== Axioms and models ==
A [[Model theory|model]] for an axiomatic system is a well-defined [[Structure (mathematical logic)|formal structure]], which assigns meaning for the undefined terms presented in the system, in a manner that is correct with the relations defined in the system. The existence of a {{Em|concrete model}} proves the [[consistency proof|consistency]] of a system{{Disputed inline||date=April 2020}}. A model is called concrete if the meanings assigned are objects and relations from the real world{{clarify|date=March 2018|reason=What does 'real world' mean in this context?}}, as opposed to an {{Em|abstract model}} which is based on other axiomatic systems.
Models can also be used to show the independence of an axiom in the system. By constructing a valid model for a subsystem without a specific axiom, we show that the omitted axiom is independent if its correctness does not necessarily follow from the subsystem.
Two models are said to be [[isomorphism|isomorphic]] if a one-to-one correspondence can be found between their elements, in a manner that preserves their relationship.<ref>{{Citation|last1=Hodges|first1=Wilfrid|title=First-order Model Theory|date=2018|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/modeltheory-fo/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Winter 2018|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=2019-10-31|last2=Scanlon|first2=Thomas}}</ref> An axiomatic system for which every model is isomorphic to another is called {{Em|categorial}} (sometimes {{Em|categorical}}). The property of categoriality (categoricity) ensures the completeness of a system, however the converse is not true: Completeness does not ensure the categoriality (categoricity) of a system, since two models can differ in properties that cannot be expressed by the [[semantics]] of the system.
==
As an example, observe the following axiomatic system, based on [[first-order logic]] with additional semantics of the following [[countably infinite]]ly many axioms added (these can be easily formalized as an [[axiom schema]]):
:<math>\exist x_1: \exist x_2: \lnot (x_1=x_2)</math> (informally, there exist two different items).
:<math>\exist x_1: \exist x_2: \exist x_3: \lnot (x_1=x_2) \land \lnot (x_1=x_3) \land \lnot (x_2=x_3)</math> (informally, there exist three different items).
:<math>...</math>
Informally, this infinite set of axioms states that there are infinitely many different items. However, the concept of an [[infinite set]] cannot be defined within the system — let alone the [[cardinality]] of such a set.
The system has at least two different models – one is the [[natural number]]s (isomorphic to any other countably infinite set), and another is the real numbers (isomorphic to any other set with the [[cardinality of the continuum]]). In fact, it has an infinite number of models, one for each cardinality of an infinite set. However, the property distinguishing these models is their cardinality — a property which cannot be defined within the system. Thus the system is not categorial. However it can be shown to be complete, for example by using the [[Łoś–Vaught test]].
== Axiomatic method ==
Stating definitions and propositions in a way such that each new term can be formally eliminated by the priorly introduced terms requires primitive notions (axioms) to avoid [[infinite regress]]. This way of doing mathematics is called the '''axiomatic method'''.<ref>"''Set Theory and its Philosophy, a Critical Introduction'' S.6; Michael Potter, Oxford, 2004</ref>
A common attitude towards the axiomatic method is [[logicism]]. In their book ''[[Principia Mathematica]]'', [[Alfred North Whitehead]] and [[Bertrand Russell]] attempted to show that all mathematical theory could be reduced to some collection of axioms. More generally, the reduction of a body of propositions to a particular collection of axioms underlies the mathematician's research program. This was very prominent in the mathematics of the twentieth century, in particular in subjects based around [[homological algebra]].
The explication of the particular axioms used in a theory can help to clarify a suitable level of abstraction that the mathematician would like to work with. For example, mathematicians opted that [[Ring (mathematics)|ring]]s need not be [[Commutative ring|commutative]], which differed from [[Emmy Noether]]'s original formulation. Mathematicians decided to consider [[topological space]]s more generally without the [[separation axiom]] which [[Felix Hausdorff]] originally formulated.
The [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]], a result of the axiomatic method applied to set theory, allowed the "proper" formulation of set-theory problems and helped avoid the paradoxes of [[Naive set theory|naïve set theory]]. One such problem was the [[continuum hypothesis]]. Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, with the historically controversial [[axiom of choice]] included, is commonly abbreviated [[ZFC]], where "C" stands for "choice". Many authors use [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory|ZF]] to refer to the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice excluded.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://mathworld.wolfram.com/Zermelo-FraenkelAxioms.html|title=Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms|last=Weisstein|first=Eric W.|website=mathworld.wolfram.com|language=en|access-date=2019-10-31}}</ref> Today ZFC is the standard form of [[axiomatic set theory]] and as such is the most common [[foundations of mathematics|foundation of mathematics]].
=== History ===
{{Further|History of mathematics}}
Mathematical methods developed to some degree of sophistication in ancient Egypt, Babylon, India, and China, apparently without employing the axiomatic method.
[[Euclid]] of [[Alexandria]] authored the earliest extant axiomatic presentation of [[Euclidean geometry]] and [[number theory]]. His idea begins with five undeniable geometric assumptions called [[axioms]]. Then, using these axioms, he established the truth of other propositions by [[Mathematical proof|proofs]], hence the axiomatic method.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Lehman |first1=Eric |last2=Meyer |first2=Albert R |last3=Leighton |first3=F Tom |title=Mathematics for Computer Science |url=https://courses.csail.mit.edu/6.042/spring17/mcs.pdf |access-date=2 May 2023}}</ref>
Many axiomatic systems were developed in the nineteenth century, including [[non-Euclidean geometry]], the foundations of [[real analysis]], [[Georg Cantor|Cantor]]'s [[set theory]], [[Gottlob Frege|Frege]]'s work on foundations, and [[David Hilbert|Hilbert]]'s 'new' use of axiomatic method as a research tool. For example, [[group theory]] was first put on an axiomatic basis towards the end of that century. Once the axioms were clarified (that [[inverse element]]s should be required, for example), the subject could proceed autonomously, without reference to the [[transformation group]] origins of those studies.
=== Example: The Peano axiomatization of natural numbers ===
{{Main|Peano axioms}}
The mathematical system of [[natural number]]s 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, ... is based on an axiomatic system first devised by the mathematician [[Giuseppe Peano]] in 1889. He chose the axioms, in the language of a single unary function symbol ''S'' (short for "[[Successor function|successor]]"), for the set of natural numbers to be:
* There is a natural number 0.
* Every natural number ''a'' has a successor, denoted by ''Sa''.
* There is no natural number whose successor is 0.
* Distinct natural numbers have distinct successors: if ''a'' ≠ ''b'', then ''Sa'' ≠ ''Sb''.
* If a property is possessed by 0 and also by the successor of every natural number it is possessed by, then it is possessed by all natural numbers ("''[[Mathematical induction#Axiom of induction|Induction axiom]]''").
=== Axiomatization and proof ===
In [[mathematics]], '''axiomatization''' is the process of taking a body of knowledge and working backwards towards its axioms. It is the formulation of a system of statements (i.e. [[axiom]]s) that relate a number of primitive terms — in order that a [[consistency proof|consistent]] body of [[Boolean-valued function|propositions]] may be derived [[deductive reasoning|deductively]] from these statements. Thereafter, the [[mathematical proof|proof]] of any proposition should be, in principle, traceable back to these axioms.
If the formal system is not [[Completeness (logic)|complete]] not every proof can be traced back to the axioms of the system it belongs. For example, a number-theoretic statement might be expressible in the language of arithmetic (i.e. the language of the Peano axioms) and a proof might be given that appeals to [[topology]] or [[complex analysis]]. It might not be immediately clear whether another proof can be found that derives itself solely from the Peano axioms.
== See also ==
{{Portal|Philosophy|Mathematics}}
{{wikiquote}}
* {{annotated link|Axiom schema}}
* {{annotated link|Formalism (philosophy of mathematics)|Formalism}}
* {{annotated link|Gödel's incompleteness theorems}}
* {{annotated link|Hilbert-style deduction system}}
* {{annotated link|History of logic}}
* {{annotated link|List of logic systems}}
* {{annotated link|Logicism}}
* {{annotated link|Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory}}, an axiomatic system for set theory and today's most common foundation for mathematics.
== References ==
{{reflist}}
== Further reading ==
* {{springer|title=Axiomatic method|id=p/a014300}}
* Eric W. Weisstein, ''Axiomatic System'', From MathWorld—A Wolfram Web Resource. [http://mathworld.wolfram.com/AxiomaticSystem.html Mathworld.wolfram.com] & [http://www.answers.com/topic/axiomatic-system Answers.com]
{{Mathematical logic}}
[[Category:Mathematical axioms|*]]
[[Category:Formal systems]]
[[Category:Methods of proof]]
|