Non-Euclidean geometry: Difference between revisions

Content deleted Content added
m Clarify reference to point A
 
Line 1:
{{Short description|Two geometries based on axioms closely related to those specifying Euclidean geometry}}
[[Image:noneuclid.png|right|thumb|400px|Behavior of lines with a common perpendicular in each of the three types of geometry]] The term '''non-Euclidean geometry''' (also spelled: '''non-Euclidian geometry''') describes both [[hyperbolic geometry|hyperbolic]] and [[elliptic geometry|elliptic]] [[geometry]], which are contrasted with [[Euclidean geometry]]. The essential difference between Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometry is the nature of [[Parallel (geometry)|parallel]] lines. In Euclidean geometry, if we start with a line ''l'' and a point ''A'', which is not on ''l'', then we can only draw one line through ''A'' that is parallel to ''l''. In hyperbolic geometry, by contrast, there are [[infinity|infinitely]] many lines through ''A'' parallel to ''l'', and in elliptic geometry, parallel lines do not exist. (See the entries on [[hyperbolic geometry]] and [[elliptic geometry]] for more information.)
{{CS1 config |mode=cs2}}
[[File:noneuclid.svg|right|thumb|400px|{{center|Behavior of lines with a common perpendicular in each of the three types of geometry}}]]
{{General geometry |branches}}
 
In [[mathematics]], '''non-Euclidean geometry''' consists of two geometries based on [[axiom]]s closely related to those that specify [[Euclidean geometry]]. As Euclidean geometry lies at the intersection of [[metric geometry]] and [[affine geometry]], non-Euclidean geometry arises by either replacing the [[parallel postulate]] with an alternative, or relaxing the metric requirement. In the former case, one obtains [[hyperbolic geometry]] and [[elliptic geometry]], the traditional non-Euclidean geometries. When the metric requirement is relaxed, then there are affine planes associated with the [[#Planar algebras|planar algebras]], which give rise to [[#Kinematic geometries|kinematic geometries]] that have also been called non-Euclidean geometry.
Another way to describe the differences between these geometries is as follows:
consider two lines in a two dimensional plane that are both [[perpendicular]] to a third line.
In Euclidean and hyperbolic geometry, the two lines are then parallel.
In Euclidean geometry, the lines remain at a constant [[distance]], while in hyperbolic geometry they "curve away" from each other, increasing their distance as one moves farther from the point of intersection with the common perpendicular.
In elliptic geometry, the lines "curve toward" each other, and eventually intersect; therefore no parallel lines exist in elliptic geometry.
 
==History Principles ==
The essential difference between the metric geometries is the nature of [[Parallel (geometry)|parallel]] lines. [[Euclid]]'s fifth postulate, the [[parallel postulate]], is equivalent to [[Playfair's Postulate|Playfair's postulate]], which states that, within a two-dimensional plane, for any given line {{mvar|l}} and a point ''A'', which is not on {{mvar|l}}, there is exactly one line through ''A'' that does not intersect {{mvar|l}}. In hyperbolic geometry, by contrast, there are [[Infinite set|infinitely]] many lines through ''A'' not intersecting {{mvar|l}}, while in elliptic geometry, any line through ''A'' intersects {{mvar|l}}.
While Euclidean geometry (named for the [[Hellenistic Greece|Greek]] [[mathematician]] [[Euclid]]) includes some of the oldest known mathematics, non-Euclidean geometries were not widely accepted as legitimate until the [[19th century]].
The debate that eventually led to the discovery of non-Euclidean geometries began almost as soon as Euclid's work ''[[Euclid's Elements|Elements]]'' was written.
In the ''Elements'', Euclid began with a limited number of assumptions (five [[axiom]]s and five postulates) and sought to prove all the other results ([[proposition]]s) in the work.
The most notorious of the postulates is often referred to as "Euclid's Fifth Postulate", or simply the "[[parallel postulate]]", which in Euclid's original formulation is:
 
Another way to describe the differences between these geometries is to consider two straight lines indefinitely extended in a two-dimensional plane that are both [[perpendicular]] to a third line (in the same plane):
:"If a straight line falls on two straight lines in such a manner that the interior angles on the same side are together less than two right angles, then the straight lines, if produced indefinitely, meet on that side on which are the angles less than the two right angles."
* In Euclidean geometry, the lines remain at a constant [[distance]] from each other (meaning that a line drawn perpendicular to one line at any point will intersect the other line and the length of the line segment joining the points of intersection remains constant) and are known as parallels.
* In hyperbolic geometry, they diverge from each other, increasing in distance as one moves further from the points of intersection with the common perpendicular; these lines are often called [[Hyperbolic geometry#Non-intersecting / parallel lines|ultraparallels]].
* In elliptic geometry, the lines converge toward each other and intersect.
 
== History ==
Other mathematicians have devised simpler forms of this property (see ''[[parallel postulate]]'' for [[equivalent]] statements). Regardless of the form of the postulate, however, it consistently appears to be more complicated than Euclid's other postulates (which include, for example, "Between any two points a straight line may be drawn").
<!-- This section is linked from [[Parallel postulate]] -->
{{see also|Euclidean geometry#History|History of geometry|Hyperbolic geometry#History}}
 
=== Background ===
For several hundred years, [[geometer]]s were troubled by the disparate complexity of the fifth postulate, and believed it could be proved as a theorem from the other four.
Many attempted to find a [[proof by contradiction]], most notably the [[Italy|Italian]] [[Giovanni Gerolamo Saccheri]].
In a work titled ''Euclides ab Omni Naevo Vindicatus'' (''Euclid Freed from All Flaws''), published in [[1733]], he quickly discarded elliptic geometry as a possibility (some others of Euclid's axioms must be modified for elliptic geometry to work) and set to work proving a great number of results in hyperbolic geometry.
He finally reached a point where he believed that his results demonstrated the impossibility of hyperbolic geometry. His claim seems to have been based on Euclidean presuppositions, because no ''logical'' contradiction was present. In this attempt to prove Euclidean geometry he instead unintentionally invented a new viable geometry. At this time it was widely believed that the universe worked according to the principles of Euclidean geometry.
 
[[Euclidean geometry]], named after the [[Greek mathematics|Greek mathematician]] [[Euclid]], includes some of the oldest known mathematics, and geometries that deviated from this were not widely accepted as legitimate until the 19th century.
A hundred years later, in [[1829]], the [[Russia]]n [[Nikolai Ivanovich Lobachevsky]] published a treatise of hyperbolic geometry.
For this reason, hyperbolic geometry is sometimes called Lobachevskian geometry.
About the same time, the [[Hungary|Hungarian]] [[János Bolyai]] also wrote a treatise on hyperbolic geometry, which was published in [[1832]] as an appendix to a work of his father's.
The great mathematician [[Carl Friedrich Gauss]] read the appendix and revealed to Bolyai that he had worked out the same results some time earlier.
 
The debate that eventually led to the discovery of the non-Euclidean geometries began almost as soon as Euclid wrote ''[[Euclid's Elements|Elements]]''. In the ''Elements'', Euclid begins with a limited number of assumptions (23 definitions, five common notions, and five postulates) and seeks to prove all the other results ([[proposition]]s) in the work. The most notorious of the postulates is often referred to as "Euclid's Fifth Postulate", or simply the ''[[parallel postulate]]'', which in Euclid's original formulation is:
Lobachevsky's name is attached by right of earliest publication. The fundamental difference between these and earlier works, such as Saccheri's, is that they were the first to unabashedly claim that Euclidean geometry was not the only geometry, nor the only conceivable geometric structure for the universe. Lobachevsky termed Euclidean geometry, "ordinary geometry," and this new hyperbolic geometry, "imaginary geometry." However, the possibility still remained that the axioms for hyperbolic geometry were logically inconsistent.
 
<blockquote>
As had been mentioned, more work on Euclid's axioms needed to be done to establish elliptic geometry.
If a straight line falls on two straight lines in such a manner that the interior angles on the same side are together less than two right angles, then the straight lines, if produced indefinitely, meet on that side on which are the angles less than the two right angles.
[[Bernhard Riemann]], in a famous lecture in [[1854]], founded the field of [[Riemannian geometry]], discussing in particular the ideas now called [[manifold]]s, [[Riemannian metric]], and [[curvature]].
</blockquote>
He constructed an infinite family of non-Euclidean geometries by giving a formula for a family of Riemannian metrics on the unit ball in [[Euclidean space]].
Sometimes he is unjustly credited with only discovering [[elliptic geometry]]; but in fact, this construction shows that his work was far-reaching, with his theorems holding for all geometries.
 
Other mathematicians have devised simpler forms of this property. Regardless of the form of the postulate, however, it consistently appears more complicated than [[Euclidean geometry#Axioms|Euclid's other postulates]]:
Euclidean geometry is [[model (abstract)|modelled]] by our notion of a "flat [[plane (mathematics)|plane]]."
# To draw a straight line from any point to any point.
# To produce [extend] a finite straight line continuously in a straight line.
# To describe a circle with any centre and distance [radius].
# That all right angles are equal to one another.
 
For at least a thousand years, [[geometer]]s were troubled by the disparate complexity of the fifth postulate, and believed it could be proved as a theorem from the other four. Many attempted to find a [[proof by contradiction]], including [[Ibn al-Haytham]] (Alhazen, 11th century),<ref>{{Citation |last=Eder |first=Michelle |year=2000 |title=Views of Euclid's Parallel Postulate in Ancient Greece and in Medieval Islam |url=http://www.math.rutgers.edu/~cherlin/History/Papers2000/eder.html |publisher=[[Rutgers University]] |access-date=2008-01-23 }}</ref> [[Omar Khayyám]] (12th century), [[Nasīr al-Dīn al-Tūsī]] (13th century), and [[Giovanni Girolamo Saccheri]] (18th century).
 
The theorems of Ibn al-Haytham, Khayyam and al-Tusi on [[quadrilateral]]s, including the [[Lambert quadrilateral]] and [[Saccheri quadrilateral]], were "the first few theorems of the [[Hyperbolic geometry|hyperbolic]] and the [[Elliptical geometry|elliptic geometries]]". These theorems along with their alternative postulates, such as [[Playfair's axiom]], played an important role in the later development of non-Euclidean geometry. These early attempts at challenging the fifth postulate had a considerable influence on its development among later European geometers, including [[Witelo]], [[Levi ben Gerson]], [[Abner of Burgos|Alfonso]], [[John Wallis]] and Saccheri.<ref>Boris A. Rosenfeld & Adolf P. Youschkevitch, "Geometry", p. 470, in Roshdi Rashed & Régis Morelon (1996), ''[[Encyclopedia of the History of Arabic Science]]'', vol. 2, pp. 447–494, [[Routledge]], London and New York: {{blockquote|"Three scientists, Ibn al-Haytham, Khayyam, and al-Tusi, had made the most considerable contribution to this branch of geometry, whose importance was completely recognized only in the nineteenth century. In essence, their propositions concerning the properties of quadrangle—which they considered assuming that some of the angles of these figures were acute of obtuse—embodied the first few theorems of the hyperbolic and the elliptic geometries. Their other proposals showed that various geometric statements were equivalent to the Euclidean postulate V. It is extremely important that these scholars established the mutual connection between this postulate and the sum of the angles of a triangle and a quadrangle. By their works on the theory of parallel lines Arab mathematicians directly influenced the relevant investigations of their European counterparts. The first European attempt to prove the postulate on parallel lines&nbsp;– made by [[Witelo]], the Polish scientists of the thirteenth century, while revising [[Ibn al-Haytham]]'s ''[[Book of Optics]]'' (''Kitab al-Manazir'')&nbsp;– was undoubtedly prompted by Arabic sources. The proofs put forward in the fourteenth century by the Jewish scholar [[Levi ben Gerson]], who lived in southern France, and by the above-mentioned Alfonso from Spain directly border on Ibn al-Haytham's demonstration. Above, we have demonstrated that ''Pseudo-Tusi's Exposition of Euclid'' had stimulated both J. Wallis's and G. [[Saccheri]]'s studies of the theory of parallel lines."}}</ref> All of these early attempts made at trying to formulate non-Euclidean geometry, however, provided flawed proofs of the parallel postulate, depending on assumptions that are now recognized as essentially equivalent to the parallel postulate. These early attempts did, however, provide some early properties of the hyperbolic and elliptic geometries.
 
Khayyam, for example, tried to derive it from an equivalent postulate he formulated from "the principles of the Philosopher" ([[Aristotle]]): "Two convergent straight lines intersect and it is impossible for two convergent straight lines to diverge in the direction in which they converge."<ref>Boris A. Rosenfeld & Adolf P. Youschkevitch (1996), "Geometry", p. 467, in Roshdi Rashed & Régis Morelon (1996), ''[[Encyclopedia of the History of Arabic Science]]'', vol. 2, pp. 447–494, [[Routledge]], {{isbn|0-415-12411-5}}</ref> Khayyam then considered the three cases right, obtuse, and acute that the summit angles of a Saccheri quadrilateral can take and after proving a number of theorems about them, he correctly refuted the obtuse and acute cases based on his postulate and hence derived the classic postulate of Euclid, which he didn't realize was equivalent to his own postulate. Another example is al-Tusi's son, Sadr al-Din (sometimes known as "Pseudo-Tusi"), who wrote a book on the subject in 1298, based on al-Tusi's later thoughts, which presented another hypothesis equivalent to the parallel postulate. "He essentially revised both the Euclidean system of axioms and postulates and the proofs of many propositions from the ''Elements''."<ref name=Katz/><ref>Boris A. Rosenfeld and Adolf P. Youschkevitch (1996), "Geometry", in Roshdi Rashed, ed., ''[[Encyclopedia of the History of Arabic Science]]'', vol. 2, pp. 447–494 [469], [[Routledge]], London and New York: {{blockquote|"In ''Pseudo-Tusi's Exposition of Euclid'', [...] another statement is used instead of a postulate. It was independent of the Euclidean postulate V and easy to prove. [...] He essentially revised both the Euclidean system of axioms and postulates and the proofs of many propositions from the ''Elements''."}}</ref> His work was published in [[Rome]] in 1594 and was studied by European geometers, including Saccheri<ref name=Katz>Victor J. Katz (1998), ''History of Mathematics: An Introduction'', pp. 270–271, [[Addison–Wesley]], {{isbn|0-321-01618-1}}: <blockquote>"But in a manuscript probably written by his son Sadr al-Din in 1298, based on Nasir al-Din's later thoughts on the subject, there is a new argument based on another hypothesis, also equivalent to Euclid's, [...] The importance of this latter work is that it was published in Rome in 1594 and was studied by European geometers. In particular, it became the starting point for the work of Saccheri and ultimately for the discovery of non-Euclidean geometry."</blockquote></ref> who criticised this work as well as that of Wallis.<ref>{{MacTutor |title= Giovanni Girolamo Saccheri |id=Saccheri }}</ref>
 
[[Giordano Vitale]], in his book ''Euclide restituo'' (1680, 1686), used the Saccheri quadrilateral to prove that if three points are equidistant on the base AB and the summit CD, then AB and CD are everywhere equidistant.
 
In a work titled ''Euclides ab Omni Naevo Vindicatus'' (''Euclid Freed from All Flaws''), published in 1733, Saccheri quickly discarded elliptic geometry as a possibility (some others of Euclid's axioms must be modified for elliptic geometry to work) and set to work proving a great number of results in hyperbolic geometry.
 
He finally reached a point where he believed that his results demonstrated the impossibility of hyperbolic geometry. His claim seems to have been based on Euclidean presuppositions, because no ''logical'' contradiction was present. In this attempt to prove Euclidean geometry he instead unintentionally discovered a new viable geometry, but did not realize it.
 
In 1766 [[Johann Heinrich Lambert|Johann Lambert]] wrote, but did not publish, ''Theorie der Parallellinien'' in which he attempted, as Saccheri did, to prove the fifth postulate. He worked with a figure now known as a ''Lambert quadrilateral'', a quadrilateral with three right angles (can be considered half of a Saccheri quadrilateral). He quickly eliminated the possibility that the fourth angle is obtuse, as had Saccheri and Khayyam, and then proceeded to prove many theorems under the assumption of an acute angle. Unlike Saccheri, he never felt that he had reached a contradiction with this assumption. He had proved the non-Euclidean result that the sum of the angles in a triangle increases as the area of the triangle decreases, and this led him to speculate on the possibility of a model of the acute case on a sphere of imaginary radius. He did not carry this idea any further.<ref>{{MacTutor |title=Johann Heinrich Lambert|id=Lambert }}</ref>
 
At this time it was widely believed that the universe worked according to the principles of Euclidean geometry.<ref>A notable exception is David Hume, who as early as 1739 seriously entertained the possibility that our universe was non-Euclidean; see David Hume (1739/1978) ''A Treatise of Human Nature'', L.A. Selby-Bigge, ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 51–52.</ref>
 
=== Development of non-Euclidean geometry ===
The beginning of the 19th century would finally witness decisive steps in the creation of non-Euclidean geometry.
Circa 1813, [[Carl Friedrich Gauss]] and independently around 1818, the German professor of law [[Ferdinand Karl Schweikart]]<ref>In a letter of December 1818, Ferdinand Karl Schweikart (1780–1859) sketched a few insights into non-Euclidean geometry. The letter was forwarded to Gauss in 1819 by Gauss's former student Gerling. In his reply to Gerling, Gauss praised Schweikart and mentioned his own, earlier research into non-Euclidean geometry. See:
* Carl Friedrich Gauss, ''Werke'' (Leipzig, Germany: B. G. Teubner, 1900), vol. 8, [http://gdz.sub.uni-goettingen.de/dms/load/img/?PPN=PPN236010751&DMDID=DMDLOG_0058&LOGID=LOG_0058&PHYSID=PHYS_0187 pp. 180–182.]
* English translations of Schweikart's letter and Gauss's reply to Gerling appear in:[http://www.math.uwaterloo.ca/~snburris/htdocs/noneucl.pdf Course notes: "Gauss and non-Euclidean geometry", University of Waterloo, Ontario, Canada]; see especially pages 10 and 11.
* Letters by Schweikart and the writings of his nephew [[Franz Adolph Taurinus]], who also was interested in non-Euclidean geometry and who in 1825 published a brief book on the parallel axiom, appear in: Paul Stäckel and Friedrich Engel, ''Die theorie der Parallellinien von Euklid bis auf Gauss, eine Urkundensammlung der nichteuklidischen Geometrie'' (The theory of parallel lines from Euclid to Gauss, an archive of non-Euclidean geometry), (Leipzig, Germany: B. G. Teubner, 1895), [http://quod.lib.umich.edu/u/umhistmath/abq9565.0001.001/254?rgn=full+text;view=pdf pages 243 ff.]</ref> had the germinal ideas of non-Euclidean geometry worked out, but neither published any results. Schweikart's nephew [[Franz Taurinus]] did publish important results of hyperbolic trigonometry in two papers in 1825 and 1826, yet while admitting the internal consistency of hyperbolic geometry, he still believed in the special role of Euclidean geometry.<ref>{{citation|author=Bonola, R.|title=Non-Euclidean geometry: A critical and historical study of its development|year=1912|___location=Chicago|publisher=Open Court|url=https://archive.org/details/noneuclideangeom00bono}}</ref>
 
Then, in 1829–1830 the [[Russia]]n mathematician [[Nikolai Ivanovich Lobachevsky]] and in 1832 the [[Hungary|Hungarian]] mathematician [[János Bolyai]] separately and independently published treatises on hyperbolic geometry. Consequently, hyperbolic geometry is called Lobachevskian or Bolyai-Lobachevskian geometry, as both mathematicians, independent of each other, are the basic authors of non-Euclidean geometry. [[Carl Friedrich Gauss|Gauss]] mentioned to Bolyai's father, when shown the younger Bolyai's work, that he had developed such a geometry several years before,<ref>In the letter to Wolfgang (Farkas) Bolyai of March 6, 1832 Gauss claims to have worked on the problem for thirty or thirty-five years {{Harvard citation|Faber|1983|loc=p. 162}}. In his 1824 letter to Taurinus {{Harvard citation|Faber|1983|loc=p. 158}} he claimed that he had been working on the problem for over 30 years and provided enough detail to show that he actually had worked out the details. According to {{harvtxt|Faber|1983|loc=p. 156}} it wasn't until around 1813 that Gauss had come to accept the existence of a new geometry.</ref> though he did not publish. While Lobachevsky created a non-Euclidean geometry by negating the parallel postulate, Bolyai worked out a geometry where both the Euclidean and the hyperbolic geometry are possible depending on a parameter&nbsp;''k''. Bolyai ends his work by mentioning that it is not possible to decide through mathematical reasoning alone if the geometry of the physical universe is Euclidean or non-Euclidean; this is a task for the physical sciences.
 
[[Bernhard Riemann]], in a famous lecture in 1854, founded the field of [[Riemannian geometry]], discussing in particular the ideas now called [[manifold]]s, [[Riemannian metric]], and [[curvature]].
He constructed an infinite family of non-Euclidean geometries by giving a formula for a family of Riemannian metrics on the unit ball in [[Euclidean space]]. The simplest of these is called [[elliptic geometry]] and it is considered a non-Euclidean geometry due to its lack of parallel lines.<ref>However, other axioms besides the parallel postulate must be changed to make this a feasible geometry.</ref>
 
By formulating the geometry in terms of a curvature [[tensor]], Riemann allowed non-Euclidean geometry to apply to higher dimensions. Beltrami (1868) was the first to apply Riemann's geometry to spaces of negative curvature.
 
=== Terminology ===
It was Gauss who coined the term "non-Euclidean geometry".<ref>Felix Klein, ''Elementary Mathematics from an Advanced Standpoint: Geometry'', Dover, 1948 (Reprint of English translation of 3rd Edition, 1940. First edition in German, 1908.) p. 176.</ref> He was referring to his own work, which today we call ''hyperbolic geometry'' or ''Lobachevskian geometry''. Several modern authors still use the generic term ''non-Euclidean geometry'' to mean ''hyperbolic geometry''.<ref>For example:
{{citation |last=Kulczycki |first=Stefan |year=1961 |title=Non-Euclidean Geometry |publisher=Pergamon |url=https://archive.org/details/noneuclideangeom0000stef/page/53 |url-access=limited |page=53 }}<br/ >
{{citation |last=Iwasawa |first=Kenkichi |year=1993 |title=Algebraic Functions |publisher=American Mathematical Society |page=140 |isbn=978-0-8218-4595-0 |url=https://archive.org/details/algebraicfunctio0000iwas/page/140/ |url-access=limited }}
</ref>
 
[[Arthur Cayley]] noted that distance between points inside a conic could be defined in terms of [[logarithm]] and the projective [[cross-ratio]] function. The method has become called the [[Cayley–Klein metric]] because [[Felix Klein]] exploited it to describe the non-Euclidean geometries in articles<ref>F. Klein, Über die sogenannte nichteuklidische Geometrie, ''Mathematische Annalen'', '''4'''(1871).</ref> in 1871 and 1873 and later in book form. The Cayley–Klein metrics provided working models of hyperbolic and elliptic metric geometries, as well as Euclidean geometry.
 
Klein is responsible for the terms "hyperbolic" and "elliptic" (in his system he called Euclidean geometry ''parabolic'', a term that generally fell out of use<ref>The Euclidean plane is still referred to as ''parabolic'' in the context of [[conformal geometry]]: see [[Uniformization theorem]].</ref>). His influence has led to the current usage of the term "non-Euclidean geometry" to mean either "hyperbolic" or "elliptic" geometry.
 
There are some mathematicians who would extend the list of geometries that should be called "non-Euclidean" in various ways.<ref>for instance, and Yaglom 1968</ref>
 
There are many kinds of geometry that are quite different from Euclidean geometry but are also not necessarily included in the conventional meaning of "non-Euclidean geometry", such as more general instances of [[Riemannian geometry]].
 
== Axiomatic basis of non-Euclidean geometry ==
Euclidean geometry can be axiomatically described in several ways. However, Euclid's original system of five postulates (axioms) is not one of these, as his proofs relied on several unstated assumptions that should also have been taken as axioms. [[Hilbert's axioms|Hilbert's system]] consisting of 20 axioms<ref>a 21st axiom appeared in the French translation of Hilbert's ''Grundlagen der Geometrie'' according to {{harvnb|Smart|1997|loc=p. 416}}</ref> most closely follows the approach of Euclid and provides the justification for all of Euclid's proofs. Other systems, using different sets of [[Primitive notion|undefined terms]] obtain the same geometry by different paths. All approaches, however, have an axiom that is logically equivalent to Euclid's fifth postulate, the parallel postulate. [[David Hilbert|Hilbert]] uses the Playfair axiom form, while [[Garrett Birkhoff|Birkhoff]], for instance, uses the axiom that says that, "There exists a pair of similar but not congruent triangles." In any of these systems, removal of the one axiom equivalent to the parallel postulate, in whatever form it takes, and leaving all the other axioms intact, produces [[absolute geometry]]. As the first 28 propositions of Euclid (in ''The Elements'') do not require the use of the parallel postulate or anything equivalent to it, they are all true statements in absolute geometry.<ref>{{Harvard citation|Smart|1997|loc=p. 366}}</ref>
 
To obtain a non-Euclidean geometry, the parallel postulate (or its equivalent) ''must'' be replaced by its [[negation]]. Negating the [[Playfair's axiom]] form, since it is a compound statement (...&nbsp;there exists one and only one&nbsp;...), can be done in two ways: either there will exist more than one line through the point parallel to the given line or there will exist no lines through the point parallel to the given line.
 
* In the first case, replacing the parallel postulate (or its equivalent) with the statement "In a plane, given a point P and a line {{mvar|l}} not passing through P, there exist two lines through P, which do not meet {{mvar|l}}" and keeping all the other axioms, yields [[hyperbolic geometry]].<ref>while only two lines are postulated, it is easily shown that there must be an infinite number of such lines.</ref>
* The second case is not dealt with as easily. Simply replacing the parallel postulate with the statement, "In a plane, given a point P and a line {{mvar|l}} not passing through P, all the lines through P meet {{mvar|l}}", does not give a consistent set of axioms. This follows since parallel lines exist in absolute geometry,<ref>Book I Proposition 27 of Euclid's ''Elements''</ref> but this statement says that there are no parallel lines. This problem was known (in a different guise) to Khayyam, Saccheri and Lambert and was the basis for their rejecting what was known as the "obtuse angle case". To obtain a consistent set of axioms that includes this axiom about having no parallel lines, some other axioms must be tweaked. These adjustments depend upon the axiom system used. Among others, these tweaks have the effect of modifying Euclid's second postulate from the statement that line segments can be extended indefinitely to the statement that lines are unbounded. [[Riemann]]'s [[elliptic geometry]] emerges as the most natural geometry satisfying this axiom.
 
== Models ==
{{comparison_of_geometries.svg}}
[[File:Triangles (spherical geometry).jpg|thumb|350px|On a sphere, the sum of the angles of a triangle is not equal to 180°. The surface of a sphere is not a Euclidean space, but locally the laws of the Euclidean geometry are good approximations. In a small triangle on the face of the earth, the sum of the angles is very near 180°.]]
 
'''Models of non-Euclidean geometry''' are [[mathematical model]]s of geometries that are non-Euclidean in the sense that it is not the case that exactly one line can be drawn [[parallel lines|parallel]] to a given line ''l'' through a point ''A'' that is not on ''l''. In hyperbolic geometric models, by contrast, there are [[infinity|infinitely]] many lines through ''A'' parallel to ''l'', and in elliptic geometric models, parallel lines do not exist. (See the entries on [[hyperbolic geometry]] and [[elliptic geometry]] for more information.)
 
Euclidean geometry is modelled by our notion of a "flat [[plane (mathematics)|plane]]."
The simplest model for elliptic geometry is a sphere, where lines are "[[great circle]]s" (such as the [[equator]] or the [[meridian (geography)|meridian]]s on a [[globe]]), and points opposite each other are identified (considered to be the same).
EvenThe after[[pseudosphere]] the work of Lobachevski, Gauss, and Bolyai,has the questionappropriate remained:[[curvature]] does such ato model exist for hyperbolic geometry? .
 
This question was answered by [[Eugenio Beltrami]], in [[1868]], who first showed that a surface called the [[pseudosphere]] has the appropriate [[curvature]] to model a portion of [[hyperbolic space]], and in a second paper in the same year, defined the [[Klein model]], the [[Poincaré disk model]], and the [[Poincaré half-plane model]] which model the entirety of hyperbolic space, and used this to show that Euclidean geometry and hyperbolic geometry were [[equiconsistent]], so that hyperbolic geometry was logically consistent if Euclidean geometry was. (The reverse implication follows from the [[horosphere]] model of Euclidean geometry.)
=== Elliptic geometry ===
{{main|Elliptic geometry}}
The simplest model for [[elliptic geometry]] is a sphere, where lines are "[[great circle]]s" (such as the [[equator]] or the [[meridian (geography)|meridian]]s on a [[globe]]), and points opposite each other (called [[antipodal points]]) are identified (considered the same). This is also one of the standard models of the [[real projective plane]]. The difference is that as a model of elliptic geometry a metric is introduced permitting the measurement of lengths and angles, while as a model of the projective plane there is no such metric.
 
In the elliptic model, for any given line {{mvar|l}} and a point ''A'', which is not on {{mvar|l}}, all lines through ''A'' will intersect {{mvar|l}}.
 
=== Hyperbolic geometry ===
{{main|Hyperbolic geometry}}
Even after the work of Lobachevsky, Gauss, and Bolyai, the question remained: "Does such a model exist for [[hyperbolic geometry]]?". The model for [[hyperbolic geometry]] was answered by [[Eugenio Beltrami]], in 1868, who first showed that a surface called the [[pseudosphere]] has the appropriate [[curvature]] to model a portion of [[hyperbolic space]] and in a second paper in the same year, defined the [[Klein model]], which models the entirety of hyperbolic space, and used this to show that Euclidean geometry and hyperbolic geometry were [[equiconsistency|equiconsistent]] so that hyperbolic geometry was [[logically consistent]] if and only if Euclidean geometry was. (The reverse implication follows from the [[horosphere]] model of Euclidean geometry.)
 
In the hyperbolic model, within a two-dimensional plane, for any given line {{mvar|l}} and a point ''A'', which is not on {{mvar|l}}, there are [[Infinite set|infinitely]] many lines through ''A'' that do not intersect {{mvar|l}}.
 
In these models, the concepts of non-Euclidean geometries are represented by Euclidean objects in a Euclidean setting. This introduces a perceptual distortion wherein the straight lines of the non-Euclidean geometry are represented by Euclidean curves that visually bend. This "bending" is not a property of the non-Euclidean lines, only an artifice of the way they are represented.
 
=== Three-dimensional non-Euclidean geometry ===
{{main|Thurston geometry}}
In three dimensions, there are eight models of geometries.<ref>* [[William Thurston]]. ''Three-dimensional geometry and topology. Vol. 1''. Edited by Silvio Levy. Princeton Mathematical Series, 35. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1997. x+311&nbsp;pp. {{isbn|0-691-08304-5}} (in depth explanation of the eight geometries and the proof that there are only eight)
</ref> There are Euclidean, elliptic, and hyperbolic geometries, as in the two-dimensional case; mixed geometries that are partially Euclidean and partially hyperbolic or spherical; twisted versions of the mixed geometries; and one unusual geometry that is completely [[anisotropy|anisotropic]] (i.e. every direction behaves differently).
 
== Uncommon properties ==
[[File:Lambert quadrilateral.svg|upright|thumb|left|{{center|Lambert quadrilateral in hyperbolic geometry}}]]
[[File:Saccheri quads.svg|150px|thumb|{{center|Saccheri quadrilaterals in the three geometries}}]]
 
Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometries naturally have many similar properties, namely those that do not depend upon the nature of parallelism. This commonality is the subject of [[absolute geometry]] (also called ''neutral geometry''). However, the properties that distinguish one geometry from others have historically received the most attention.
 
Besides the behavior of lines with respect to a common perpendicular, mentioned in the introduction, we also have the following:
* A [[Lambert quadrilateral]] is a quadrilateral with three right angles. The fourth angle of a Lambert quadrilateral is [[Acute angle|acute]] if the geometry is hyperbolic, a [[right angle]] if the geometry is Euclidean or [[Obtuse angle|obtuse]] if the geometry is elliptic. Consequently, [[rectangle]]s exist (a statement equivalent to the parallel postulate) only in Euclidean geometry.
* A [[Saccheri quadrilateral]] is a quadrilateral with two sides of equal length, both perpendicular to a side called the ''base''. The other two angles of a Saccheri quadrilateral are called the ''summit angles'' and they have equal measure. The summit angles of a Saccheri quadrilateral are acute if the geometry is hyperbolic, right angles if the geometry is Euclidean and obtuse angles if the geometry is elliptic.
* The sum of the measures of the angles of any triangle is less than 180° if the geometry is hyperbolic, equal to 180° if the geometry is Euclidean, and greater than 180° if the geometry is elliptic. The ''defect'' of a triangle is the numerical value (180° &minus; the sum of the measures of the angles of the triangle). This result may also be stated as: the defect of triangles in hyperbolic geometry is positive, the defect of triangles in Euclidean geometry is zero, and the defect of triangles in elliptic geometry is negative.
 
== Importance ==
Before the models of a non-Euclidean plane were presented by Beltrami, Klein, and Poincaré, Euclidean geometry stood unchallenged as the [[mathematical model]] of [[space]]. Furthermore, since the substance of the subject in [[synthetic geometry]] was a chief exhibit of rationality, the Euclidean point of view represented absolute authority.
 
The discovery of the non-Euclidean geometries had a ripple effect which went far beyond the boundaries of mathematics and science. The philosopher [[Immanuel Kant]]'s treatment of human knowledge had a special role for geometry. It was his prime example of synthetic [[a priori]] knowledge; not derived from the senses nor deduced through logic&nbsp;— our knowledge of space was a truth that we were born with. Unfortunately for Kant, his concept of this unalterably true geometry was Euclidean. Theology was also affected by the change from absolute truth to relative truth in the way that mathematics is related to the world around it, that was a result of this paradigm shift.<ref>Imre Toth, "Gott und Geometrie: Eine viktorianische Kontroverse," ''Evolutionstheorie und ihre Evolution'', Dieter Henrich, ed. (Schriftenreihe der Universität Regensburg, band 7, 1982) pp. 141–204.</ref>
 
Non-Euclidean geometry is an example of a [[paradigm shift|scientific revolution]] in the [[history of science]], in which mathematicians and scientists changed the way they viewed their subjects.<ref>see {{harvnb|Trudeau|2001|loc=pp. vii–viii}}</ref> Some geometers called [[Nikolai Lobachevsky|Lobachevsky]] the "[[Copernicus]] of Geometry" due to the revolutionary character of his work.<ref>{{citation|last=Bell|first=E. T.|author-link=E. T. Bell|title=Men of Mathematics|year=1986|publisher=Touchstone Books|isbn=978-0-671-62818-5|page=294}} Author attributes this quote to another mathematician, [[William Kingdon Clifford]].</ref><ref>This is a quote from G. B. Halsted's translator's preface to his 1914 translation of ''The Theory of Parallels'': "What [[Vesalius]] was to [[Galen]], what [[Copernicus]] was to [[Ptolemy]] that was Lobachevsky to [[Euclid]]." &mdash; [[William Kingdon Clifford|W. K. Clifford]]</ref>
 
The existence of non-Euclidean geometries impacted the intellectual life of [[Victorian England]] in many ways<ref>{{Harvard citation|Richards|1988}}</ref> and in particular was one of the leading factors that caused a re-examination of the teaching of geometry based on [[Euclid's Elements]]. This curriculum issue was hotly debated at the time and was even the subject of a book, ''[[Euclid and his Modern Rivals]]'', written by Charles Lutwidge Dodgson (1832–1898) better known as [[Lewis Carroll]], the author of ''[[Alice's Adventures in Wonderland|Alice in Wonderland]]''.
 
== Planar algebras ==
In [[analytic geometry]] a [[plane (geometry)|plane]] is described with [[Cartesian coordinate]]s:
: <math>C = \{ (x,y) : x,y \isin \mathbb{R} \}</math>
 
The [[point (geometry)|point]]s are sometimes identified with generalized complex numbers {{math|1=''z'' = ''x'' + ''y'' ε}} where ε<sup>2</sup> ∈ {{mset| –1, 0, 1 }}.
 
The Euclidean plane corresponds to the case {{math|1=ε<sup>2</sup> = &minus;1}}, an [[imaginary unit]]. Since the modulus of {{mvar|z}} is given by
: <math>z z^\ast = (x + y \epsilon) (x - y \epsilon) = x^2 + y^2 ,</math> this quantity is the square of the [[Euclidean distance]] between {{mvar|z}} and the origin.
For instance, {{math|1={''z'' {{!}} ''z z''* = 1} }} is the [[unit circle]].
 
For planar algebra, non-Euclidean geometry arises in the other cases.
When {{math|1=ε<sup>2</sup> = +1}}, a [[hyperbolic unit]]. Then {{mvar|z}} is a [[split-complex number]] and conventionally {{math|'''j'''}} replaces epsilon. Then
: <math>z z^\ast = (x + y\mathbf{j}) (x - y\mathbf{j}) = x^2 - y^2 \!</math>
and {{math|1={''z'' {{!}} ''z z''* = 1} }} is the [[unit hyperbola]].
 
When {{math|1=ε<sup>2</sup> = 0}}, then {{mvar|z}} is a [[dual number]].<ref>[[Isaak Yaglom]] (1968) ''Complex Numbers in Geometry'', translated by E. Primrose from 1963 Russian original, appendix "Non-Euclidean geometries in the plane and complex numbers", pp, 195–219, [[Academic Press]], N.Y.</ref>
 
This approach to non-Euclidean geometry explains the non-Euclidean angles: the parameters of [[slope]] in the dual number plane and [[hyperbolic angle]] in the split-complex plane correspond to [[angle]] in Euclidean geometry. Indeed, they each arise in [[polar decomposition#Alternative planar decompositions|polar decomposition]] of a complex number {{mvar|z}}.<ref>[[Richard C. Tolman]] (2004) ''Theory of Relativity of Motion'', p. 194, §180 Non-Euclidean angle, §181 Kinematical interpretation of angle in terms of velocity</ref>
 
== Kinematic geometries ==
The development of non-Euclidean geometries proved very important to physics in the [[20th century]]. Given the limitation of the [[speed of light]], velocity additions necessitate the use of [[hyperbolic geometry]].
Hyperbolic geometry found an application in [[kinematics]] with the [[physical cosmology]] introduced by [[Hermann Minkowski]] in 1908. Minkowski introduced terms like [[worldline]] and [[proper time]] into [[mathematical physics]]. He realized that the [[submanifold]], of events one moment of proper time into the future, could be considered a [[hyperbolic space]] of three dimensions.<ref>Hermann Minkowski (1908–9). [[s:Space and Time|"Space and Time"]] (Wikisource).</ref><ref>Scott Walter (1999) [http://www.univ-nancy2.fr/DepPhilo/walter/papers/nes.pdf Non-Euclidean Style of Special Relativity]</ref>
[[Albert Einstein|Einstein]]'s [[Theory of Relativity]] describes space as generally flat (i.e., Euclidean), but elliptically curved (i.e., non-Euclidean) in regions near where matter is present. Because the universe expands (see the [[hubble constant]]), the space where no matter exists could be described by using a hyperbolic model.
Already in the 1890s [[Alexander Macfarlane]] was charting this submanifold through his ''Algebra of Physics'' and [[hyperbolic quaternion]]s, though Macfarlane did not use cosmological language as Minkowski did in 1908. The relevant structure is now called the [[hyperboloid model]] of hyperbolic geometry.
This kind of geometry, where the curvature changes from point to point, is called [[riemannian geometry]].
 
The non-Euclidean planar algebras support kinematic geometries in the plane. For instance, the [[split-complex number]] ''z'' = e<sup>''a''j</sup> can represent a spacetime event one moment into the future of a [[frame of reference]] of [[rapidity]] ''a''. Furthermore, multiplication by ''z'' amounts to a [[Lorentz boost]] mapping the frame with rapidity zero to that with rapidity ''a''.
There are other mathematical models of the plane in which the parallel postulate fails, for example the [[Dehn plane]] consisting of all points (x,y), where x and y are finite [[surreal numbers]].
 
Kinematic study makes use of the [[dual number]]s <math>z = x + y \epsilon, \quad \epsilon^2 = 0,</math> to represent the classical description of motion in [[absolute time and space]]:
==References==
The equations <math>x^\prime = x + vt,\quad t^\prime = t</math> are equivalent to a [[shear mapping]] in linear algebra:<math>\begin{pmatrix}x' \\ t' \end{pmatrix} = \begin{pmatrix}1 & v \\ 0 & 1 \end{pmatrix}\begin{pmatrix}x \\ t \end{pmatrix}.</math>
:
With dual numbers the mapping is <math>t^\prime + x^\prime \epsilon = (1 + v \epsilon)(t + x \epsilon) = t + (x + vt)\epsilon.</math><ref>[[Isaak Yaglom]] (1979) A simple non-Euclidean geometry and its physical basis : an elementary account of Galilean geometry and the Galilean principle of relativity, Springer {{isbn|0-387-90332-1}}</ref>
 
Another view of [[special relativity]] as a non-Euclidean geometry was advanced by [[Edwin Bidwell Wilson|E. B. Wilson]] and [[Gilbert N. Lewis|Gilbert Lewis]] in ''Proceedings of the [[American Academy of Arts and Sciences]]'' in 1912. They revamped the analytic geometry implicit in the split-complex number algebra into [[synthetic geometry]] of premises and deductions.<ref>[[Edwin B. Wilson]] & [[Gilbert N. Lewis]] (1912) "The Space-time Manifold of Relativity. The Non-Euclidean Geometry of Mechanics and Electromagnetics" Proceedings of the [[American Academy of Arts and Sciences]] 48:387–507</ref><ref>[https://web.archive.org/web/20091027012400/http://ca.geocities.com/cocklebio/synsptm.html Synthetic Spacetime], a digest of the axioms used, and theorems proved, by Wilson and Lewis. Archived by [[WebCite]]</ref>
*James W. Anderson, ''Hyperbolic Geometry'', second edition, Springer, 2005
 
== Fiction ==
*Eugenio Beltrami, ''Theoria fondamentale delgi spazil di curvatura constanta'', Annali. di Mat., ser II 2 (1868), 232-255
Non-Euclidean geometry often makes appearances in works of [[science fiction]] and [[fantasy]].
* In 1895, [[H. G. Wells]] published the short story "The Remarkable Case of Davidson's Eyes". To appreciate this story one should know how [[antipodal points]] on a sphere are identified in a model of the elliptic plane. In the story, in the midst of a thunderstorm, Sidney Davidson sees "Waves and a remarkably neat schooner" while working in an electrical laboratory at Harlow Technical College. At the story's close, Davidson proves to have witnessed H.M.S. ''Fulmar'' off [[Antipodes Island]].
* Non-Euclidean geometry is sometimes connected with the influence of the 20th-century [[horror fiction]] writer [[H. P. Lovecraft]]. In his works, many unnatural things follow their own unique laws of geometry: in Lovecraft's [[Cthulhu Mythos]], the sunken city of [[R'lyeh]] is characterized by its non-Euclidean geometry. It is heavily implied this is achieved as a side effect of not following the natural laws of this universe rather than simply using an alternate geometric model, as the sheer innate wrongness of it is said to be capable of driving those who look upon it insane.<ref>{{cite web|title=The Call of Cthulhu|url=http://www.hplovecraft.com/writings/texts/fiction/cc.aspx}}</ref>
* The main character in [[Robert Pirsig]]'s ''[[Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance]]'' mentioned [[Riemannian geometry]] on multiple occasions.
* In ''[[The Brothers Karamazov]]'', Dostoevsky discusses non-Euclidean geometry through his character Ivan.
* Christopher Priest's novel ''[[Inverted World]]'' describes the struggle of living on a planet with the form of a rotating [[pseudosphere]].
* Robert Heinlein's ''[[The Number of the Beast (novel)|The Number of the Beast]]'' utilizes non-Euclidean geometry to explain instantaneous transport through space and time and between parallel and fictional universes.
* Zeno Rogue's ''[[HyperRogue]]'' is a [[roguelike]] game set on the [[hyperbolic plane]], allowing the player to experience many properties of this geometry. Many mechanics, quests, and locations are strongly dependent on the features of hyperbolic geometry.<ref>{{cite web|title=HyperRogue website|url=http://www.roguetemple.com/z/hyper/}}</ref>
* In the [[Renegade Legion]] [[science fiction]] setting for [[FASA]]'s [[Wargame (video games)|wargame]], [[role-playing-game]] and fiction, [[faster-than-light travel]] and communications is possible through the use of Hsieh Ho's Polydimensional Non-Euclidean Geometry, published sometime in the middle of the 22nd century.
* In [[Ian Stewart (mathematician)|Ian Stewart's]] ''[[Flatterland]]'' the [[protagonist]] Victoria Line visits all kinds of non-Euclidean worlds.
 
== See also ==
*[[Ian Stewart (mathematician)|Ian Stewart]], <cite>[[Flatterland]]</cite>. New York: Perseus Publishing, 2001. ISBN 0-7382-0675-X (softcover)
* {{slink|Euclidean space#Other geometric spaces}}
* [[Hyperbolic space]]
* [[Lénárt sphere]]
* [[Projective geometry]]
* [[Non-Euclidean surface growth]]
* {{slink|Parallel (geometry)#In non-Euclidean geometry}}
* {{slink|Spherical geometry#Relation to similar geometries}}
 
== Notes ==
*Marvin Jay Greenberg, <cite>Euclidean and pseudo-Euclidean geometries: Development and history</cite> New York: W. H. Freeman, 1993. ISBN 0716724464
{{reflist|30em}}
 
==External linksReferences ==
* {{citation |last1=A'Campo |first1=Norbert |title=Strasbourg Master Class on Geometry |last2=Papadopoulos |first2=Athanase |date=2012 |publisher=European Mathematical Society |isbn=978-3-03719-105-7 |___location=Zürich, Switzerland |pages=1–182 |chapter=Notes on non-Euclidean geometry |doi=10.4171/105-1/1 |oclc=776505866}}
*[http://www-groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/HistTopics/Non-Euclidean_geometry.html MacTutor Archive article on non-Euclidean geometry]
* {{citation |last=Anderson |first=James W. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=mjb0BwAAQBAJ |title=Hyperbolic Geometry |date=1999 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-85233-156-6 |___location=London }}
* {{citation |last=Beltrami |first=Eugenio |date=1868 |title=[[s:it:Teoria fondamentale degli spazii di curvatura costante|Teoria fondamentale degli spazii di curvatura costante]] |journal=Annali di Matematica |volume=2 |issue=1 |pages=232–255|doi=10.1007/BF02419615 }}
* {{citation |last=Blumenthal |first=Leonard M. |title=A Modern View of Geometry |publisher=Dover |year=1980 |isbn=978-0-486-63962-8 |___location=Mineola, NY }}
* {{citation |last=Carrol |first=Lewis |author-link=Lewis Carroll |title=Euclid and His Modern Rivals |title-link=Euclid and His Modern Rivals |date=1879 |publisher=MacMillan |___location=London}}
* {{citation |last=Coxeter |first=H. S. M. |author-link=Harold Scott MacDonald Coxeter |url=https://archive.org/details/mathematicalexpo0000hsmc |title=Non-Euclidean Geometry |date=1961 |publisher=University of Toronto Press |edition=4th |___location=Toronto |orig-date=1942 |url-access=registration}}
* {{citation |last=Faber |first=Richard L. |url=https://archive.org/details/foundationsofeuc0000fabe |title=Foundations of Euclidean and Non-Euclidean Geometry |publisher=Dekker |year=1983 |isbn=978-0-8247-1748-3 |___location=New York |url-access=registration}}
* {{citation |last=Gray |first=Jeremy |url=https://archive.org/details/ideasofspaceeucl0000gray |title=Ideas of Space: Euclidean, Non-Euclidean, and Relativistic |date=1989 |publisher=Clarendon Press |___location=Oxford |isbn=978-0-19-853935-3 |edition=2nd |orig-date=1979 |url-access=registration}}
* {{citation |last=Greenberg |first=Marvin J. |author-link=Marvin Greenberg |title=Euclidean and Non-Euclidean Geometries: Development and History |date=2008 |publisher=W.H. Freeman |isbn=978-0-7167-9948-1 |edition=4th |___location=New York}}
* {{citation |last=Kline |first=Morris |author-link=Morris Kline |url=https://archive.org/details/mathematicalthou0000unse |title=Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times |date=1972 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-501496-9 |___location=New York |page=861-81 |url-access=registration}}
* {{citation |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=70JEFMFNIOYC |title=A New Perspective on Relativity: An Odyssey in Non-Euclidean Geometries |date=2012 |publisher=World Scientific |isbn=978-981-4340-49-6 |editor-last=Lavenda |editor-first=Bernard H. |editor-link=Bernard H. Lavenda |___location=Singapore |doi=10.1142/9789814340496_0001 |bibcode=2012npro.book.....L }}
* {{citation |last=Lobačevskij |first=Nikolaj I. |author-link=Nikolai Lobachevsky |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=p15epMkyx0UC |title=Pangeometry |date=2010 |publisher=European Mathematical Society |isbn=978-3-03719-087-6 |___location=Zürich |translator-last=Papadopoulos |translator-first=Athanase}}
* {{citation |last=Manning |first=Henry Parker |title=Non-Euclidean Geometry |year=1901 |url=https://gutenberg.org/ebooks/13702}}
* {{citation |last=Meschkowski |first=Herbert |title=Noneuclidean Geometry |publisher=Academic Press |year=1964 |___location=New York |translator-last=Shenitzer |translator-first=A.}}
* {{citation |last=Milnor |first=John W. |date=1982 |title=Hyperbolic geometry: The first 150 years |url=http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.bams/1183548588 |journal=Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society |volume=6 |issue=1 |pages=9–24 |doi=10.1090/S0273-0979-1982-14958-8 |doi-access=free }}
* {{citation |last=Richards |first=Joan L. |author-link=Joan L. Richards |title=Mathematical Visions: The Pursuit of Geometry in Victorian England |publisher=Academic Press |year=1988 |isbn=978-0-12-587445-8 |___location=Boston}}
* {{citation |last=Smart |first=James R. |title=Modern Geometries |publisher=Brooks/Cole |year=1997 |isbn=978-0-534-35188-5 |edition=5. |___location=Pacific Grove, CA}}
* {{citation |last=Stewart |first=Ian |author-link=Ian Stewart (mathematician) |title=Flatterland: Like Flatland, Only More So |title-link=Flatterland |date=2001 |publisher=Perseus Books |isbn=978-0-7382-0675-2 |___location=Cambridge, MA}}
* {{citation |last=Stillwell |first=John |author-link=John Stillwell |url=https://archive.org/details/sourcesofhyperbo0000stil |title=Sources of Hyperbolic Geometry |date=1996 |publisher=American Mathematical Society |isbn=978-0-8218-0529-9 |___location=Providence, RI |url-access=registration}}
* {{citation |last=Trudeau |first=Richard J. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1oMHCAAAQBAJ |title=The Non-Euclidean Revolution |publisher=Birkhäuser |year=2001 |isbn=978-1-4612-2102-9 |___location=Boston |orig-date=1987}}
* {{citation |last=Lambert |first=Johann Heinrich |title=La théorie des lignes parallèles de Johann Heinrich Lambert |date=2014 |publisher=Librairie Albert Blanchard |isbn=978-2-85367-266-5 |editor-last=Papadopoulos |editor-first=Athanase |___location=Paris |editor-last2=Théret |editor-first2=Guillaume}}
 
==See alsoExternal links ==
* {{Commons category-inline}}
*[[Projective geometry]]
{{wikiquote}}
*[[Spherical geometry]]
* Roberto Bonola (1912) ''[https://archive.org/details/noneuclideangeom00bonorich Non-Euclidean Geometry]'', Open Court, Chicago.
*[[Taxicab geometry]]
* {{MacTutor |class=HistTopics |title=Non-Euclidean Geometry|id=Non-Euclidean_geometry }}
*[[Hyperbolic geometry]]
* [http://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php/Non-Euclidean_geometries "Non-Euclidean geometries"] from ''Encyclopedia of Math'' of [[European Mathematical Society]] and Springer
*[[Hyperbolic space]]
* [https://web.archive.org/web/20091027012400/http://ca.geocities.com/cocklebio/synsptm.html Synthetic Spacetime], a digest of the axioms used, and theorems proved, by Wilson and Lewis. Archived by [[WebCite]].
 
[[Category:{{Geometry]]-footer}}
{{Positivism}}
{{Authority control}}
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Non-Euclidean Geometry}}
[[bg:Неевклидова геометрия]]
[[Category:Non-Euclidean geometry| ]]
[[da:Ikke-euklidisk geometri]]
[[de:Nichteuklidische Geometrie]]
[[fa:هندسه‌ نااقليدسی]]
[[fr:Géométrie non euclidienne]]
[[ko:비유클리드 기하학]]
[[it:Geometrie non euclidee]]
[[he:גאומטריה לא אוקלידית]]
[[nl:Niet-euclidische meetkunde]]
[[ja:非ユークリッド幾何学]]
[[pl:Geometria nieeuklidesowa]]
[[sv:Icke-euklidisk geometri]]
[[vi:Hình học phi Euclide]]
[[zh:非欧几里德几何]]