Immanuel Kant: Difference between revisions

Content deleted Content added
m Aesthetics: Added citations
 
Line 1:
{{Short description|German philosopher (1724–1804)}}
{{Infobox_Philosopher |
{{Redirect|Kant|other uses|Kant (disambiguation)}}
<!-- Scroll down to edit this page -->
{{Use dmy dates|date=November 2024}}
<!-- Philosopher Category -->
{{Infobox philosopher
region = Western Philosophers |
<!--PLEASE EDIT ONLY IF FAMILIAR WITH THE POLICIES OUTLINED AT [[MOS:INFOBOX]].
era = [[18th-century philosophy]],<br>[[Age of Enlightenment]] |
color = #B0C4DE |
 
In particular:
<!-- Image and Caption -->
* "The less information it contains, the more effectively it serves that purpose, allowing readers to identify key facts at a glance. Of necessity, some infoboxes contain more than just a few fields; however, wherever possible, present information in short form, and exclude any unnecessary content."
image_name = kant.jpg |
* Everything in the Infobox must be supported by the article itself. Anything that requires a citation does not belong.
image_caption = Immanuel Kant in middle age |
* With respect to lists or catalogs, longer is not better. If it is not possible to be comprehensive, a list will invariably become arbitrary. Unless it is clear from the article itself what does and does not belong, that category probably should not be in the Infobox at all.
* Those interested in creating and tending longer lists might consider [[Wikipedia:Stand-alone lists]], to which the article could then link with a "See also" wherever most appropriate.
 
Thank you for helping to minimize bloat and keep everything reader-friendly!
<!-- Information -->
-->
name = Immanuel Kant|
| name = Immanuel Kant
birth = [[April 22]], [[1724]] ([[Königsberg]], [[Germany]]) (Now [[Kaliningrad]], [[Russia]]) |
| birth_name=Emanuel Kant
death = [[February 12]], [[1804]] ([[Königsberg]], [[Germany]]) |
| image = Immanuel Kant - Gemaelde 1.jpg
school_tradition = [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] |
| caption = Portrait of Kant, 1768
main_interests = [[Epistemology]], [[Metaphysics]], [[Ethics]] |
| birth_date = {{birth date|1724|4|22|df=yes}}
influences = [[David Hume|Hume]], [[René Descartes|Descartes]], [[Nicolas Malebranche|Malebranche]], [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]], [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[George Berkeley|Berkeley]], [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau|Rousseau]] |
| birth_place = [[Königsberg]], Prussia
influenced = [[Johann Fichte|Fichte]], [[Friedrich Schelling|Schelling]], [[Georg Hegel|Hegel]], [[Arthur Schopenhauer|Schopenhauer]], [[Charles Peirce|Peirce]], [[Friedrich Nietzsche|Nietzsche]], [[Ludwig Wittgenstein|Wittgenstein]], [[Edmund Husserl|Husserl]], [[Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]], [[Jean-Paul Sartre|Sartre]], [[Jürgen Habermas|Habermas]], [[Otto Weininger|Weininger]] and many more not listed here
| death_date = {{nowrap|{{death date and age|df=yes|1804|2|12|1724|4|22}}}}
|
| death_place = Königsberg, Prussia
notable_ideas = [[Categorical imperative]], [[Transcendental Idealism]], [[Synthetic proposition|Synthetic a priori]], [[Noumenon]] |
| education = {{Plain list|
* [[University of Königsberg]] ([[Bachelor of Arts|BA]]; [[Master of Arts|MA]], 1755; [[PhD]], 1755; PhD, 1770)
}}
| institutions = University of Königsberg
| thesis1_title = New Elucidation of the First Principles of Metaphysical Cognition
| thesis1_url = https://korpora.zim.uni-duisburg-essen.de/kant/aa01/385.html
| thesis1_year = September 1755
| thesis2_title = On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and Intelligible Worlds
| thesis2_url = https://books.google.com/books?id=dNRKAQAAMAAJ&pg=PA123&redir_esc=y
| thesis2_year = August 1770
| region = [[Western philosophy]]
| era = [[Age of Enlightenment]]
| main_interests = [[Aesthetics]], [[epistemology]], [[ethics]], [[metaphysics]], [[systematic philosophy]]
| school_tradition = {{Plainlist|
* [[Enlightenment philosophy]]
* [[Kantianism]]
}}
{{Collapsible list|title={{nobold|''Other schools''}}
| [[Classical liberalism]]
| [[Empirical realism]]
| [[German idealism]]
| [[Liberal naturalism]]
| [[Transcendental idealism]]
}}
| notable_ideas = {{collapsible list|title={{nothing}}
| [[Aesthetic judgment|Aesthetic]]–[[teleological judgment]]s
| [[Analytic–synthetic distinction]]
| [[Categorical imperative|Categorical]] and [[hypothetical imperative]]
| [[Category (Kant)|Categories]]
| [[Critical philosophy]]
| [[Copernican Revolution#Immanuel Kant|Copernican revolution]] in philosophy
| [[Aesthetic distance|Disinterested delight]]
| [[Empirical realism]]
| [[Kant's antinomies]]
| [[Kantian ethics]]
| [[Kingdom of Ends]]
| [[Nebular hypothesis]]
| [[Schema (Kant)|Transcendental schema]]
| [[Theoretical philosophy|Theoretical]] vs. [[practical philosophy]]
| [[Transcendental idealism]]
| [[Transcendental subject]]
| [[Understanding (Kant)|Understanding–reason distinction]]
}}
| signature = Immanuel Kant signature.svg
| signature_alt = Signature written in ink in a flowing script
| academic_advisors = [[Martin Knutzen]], [[Johann Gottfried Teske]] (M.A. advisor)
| notable_students = [[Jakob Sigismund Beck]], [[Johann Gottfried Herder]], [[Karl Leonhard Reinhold]] (epistolary correspondent)
}}
{{Immanuel Kant}}
 
'''Immanuel Kant'''{{efn|{{IPAc-en|UK|k|æ|n|t}},<ref>[https://www.collinsdictionary.com/dictionary/english/kant "Kant"] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190927133528/https://www.collinsdictionary.com/dictionary/english/kant |date=27 September 2019 }}. ''[[Collins English Dictionary]]''.</ref><ref>[http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/kant "Kant"] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141023143832/http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/kant |date=23 October 2014 }}. ''[[Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary]]''.</ref> {{IPAc-en|US|k|ɑː|n|t}};<ref>{{cite LPD|3}}</ref><ref>{{cite EPD|18}}</ref> {{IPA|de|ɪˈmaːnu̯eːl kant|lang}}<ref>{{cite web|url=https://www.duden.de/rechtschreibung/Immanuel_maennlicher_Vorname|title=Immanuel|work=[[Duden]]|access-date=20 October 2018|language=de|archive-date=20 December 2020|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20201220055817/https://www.duden.de/rechtschreibung/Immanuel_maennlicher_Vorname|url-status=live}}</ref><ref>{{cite web|url=https://www.duden.de/rechtschreibung/Kant|title=Kant|work=Duden|access-date=20 October 2018|language=de|archive-date=20 October 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20181020182053/https://www.duden.de/rechtschreibung/Kant|url-status=live}}</ref>}} (born '''Emanuel Kant'''; 22 April 1724&nbsp;– 12 February 1804) was a German<!--"German" is the consensus after intensive talking--> philosopher and one of the central thinkers of the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]]. Born in [[Königsberg]], Kant's comprehensive and systematic works in [[epistemology]], [[metaphysics]], [[ethics]], and [[aesthetics]] have made him one of the most influential and highly discussed figures in modern [[Western philosophy]].
'''Immanuel Kant''' ([[22 April]], [[1724]] &ndash; [[12 February]], [[1804]]), was a [[German people|German]] [[philosopher]] from [[Königsberg]] (now Kaliningrad) in [[East Prussia]]. Kant is often considered one of the greatest, and is one of the most influential thinkers of [[modern Europe]] and the last major philosopher of the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]].
 
In his doctrine of [[transcendental idealism]], Kant argued that [[space]] and [[time]] are mere "forms of intuition [{{Langx|de|[[Anschauung]]|links=no}}]" that structure all [[experience]] and that the objects of experience are mere "appearances". The nature of things as they are in themselves is unknowable to us. Nonetheless, in an attempt to counter the philosophical doctrine of [[Philosophical skepticism|skepticism]], he wrote the ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'' (1781/1787), his best-known work. Kant drew a parallel to the [[Copernican Revolution#Immanuel Kant|Copernican Revolution]] in his proposal to think of the objects of experience as conforming to people's spatial and temporal forms of [[Anschauung|intuition]] and the [[Category (Kant)|categories]] of their understanding so that they have ''[[A priori and a posteriori|a priori]]'' cognition of those objects.
==Kant and his philosophy==
Kant defined the Enlightenment, in the essay "[[What is Enlightenment?|Answering the Question: What is Enlightenment?]]", as an age shaped by the motto, "Dare to know" (latin: ''[[Sapere aude]]''). This involved thinking [[autonomy|autonomously]], free of the dictates of external [[authority]]. Kant's work served as a bridge between the [[Continental rationalism|Rationalist]] and [[Empiricism|Empiricist]] traditions of the [[18th century]]. He had a decisive impact on the [[Romanticism|Romantic]] and [[German Idealism|German Idealist]] philosophies of the [[19th century]]. His work has also been a starting point for many [[20th century]] philosophers.
 
Kant believed that [[reason]] is the source of [[morality]] and that aesthetics arises from a faculty of disinterested judgment. Kant's religious views were deeply connected to his moral theory. Their exact nature remains in dispute. He hoped that perpetual peace could be secured through an international federation of [[Republicanism|republican]] states and [[Multilateralism|international cooperation]]. His [[Cosmopolitanism|cosmopolitan]] reputation is called into question by his promulgation of [[scientific racism]] for much of his career, although he altered his views on the subject in the last decade of his life.
The two interconnected foundations of what Kant called his "[[critical philosophy]]" of the "[[Copernican revolution]]" which he claimed to have wrought in philosophy were his [[epistemology]] (or [[theory of knowledge]]) of [[transcendental idealism|Transcendental Idealism]] and his [[moral philosophy]] of the autonomy of reason. These placed the active, rational human [[subject (philosophy)|subject]] at the center of the cognitive and moral worlds. With regard to knowledge, Kant argued that the rational order of the world as known by science could never be accounted for merely by the fortuitous accumulation of sense perceptions. It was instead the product of the rule-based activity of "synthesis". This consisted of conceptual unification and integration carried out by the mind through [[concepts]] or the "categories of the understanding" operating on perceptions within [[space and time]], which are not concepts, but forms of sensibility that are necessary conditions for any possible experience. Thus the objective order of nature and the causal necessity that operates within it are products of the mind in its interaction with what lies outside of mind (the "thing-in-itself"). With regard to [[morality]], Kant argued that the source of the [[Goodness and value theory|good]] lies not in anything outside the [[human]] subject, either in [[nature]] or given by [[God]], but rather only in a good will. A good will is one that acts in accordance with universal moral laws that the autonomous human being freely gives itself. These laws obligate people to treat other human beings as ends rather than as (merely) means to an end.
 
==Early life==
These Kantian ideas have largely framed or influenced all subsequent philosophical discussion and analysis. The specifics of Kant's account generated immediate and lasting controversy. Nevertheless, his theses that the [[mind]] itself makes a constitutive contribution to its [[knowledge]], which is therefore subject to limits that cannot be overcome, that morality is rooted in human freedom and acting autonomously is to act according to rational moral principles, and that philosophy involves self-critical activity, irrevocably reshaped philosophy.
Immanuel Kant was born on 22 April 1724 into a [[Prussia]]n German family of [[Lutheranism|Lutheran]] faith in [[Königsberg]] in [[East Prussia]]. His mother, Anna Regina Reuter, was born in Königsberg to a father from [[Nuremberg]].<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.koenigsberg-is-dead.de/I_Cosmopolis.html |title=Cosmopolis |website=Koenigsberg-is-dead.de |date=23 April 2001 |access-date=24 July 2009 |archive-date=22 March 2009 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090322094741/http://www.koenigsberg-is-dead.de/I_Cosmopolis.html |url-status=live}}</ref> Her surname is sometimes erroneously given as Porter. Kant's father, Johann Georg Kant, was a German harness-maker from [[Klaipėda|Memel]],{{sfn|Kuehn|2001|p=26}} at the time Prussia's most northeastern city (now [[Klaipėda]], Lithuania). It is possible that the Kants got their name from the village of Kantvainiai (German: ''Kantwaggen'' – today part of [[Priekulė, Lithuania|Priekulė]]) and were of [[Kursenieki]] origin.<ref>R.K. Murray, "The Origin of Immanuel Kant's Family Name", ''Kantian Review'' '''13'''(1), March 2008, pp. 190–193.</ref><ref>Rosa Kohlheim, Volker Kohlheim, ''Duden – Familiennamen: Herkunft und Bedeutung von 20.000 Nachnamen'', Bibliographisches Institut & F.A. Brockhaus AG, Mannheim 2005, p. 365.</ref>
 
Kant was baptized as Emanuel and later changed the spelling of his name to Immanuel after learning [[Hebrew language|Hebrew]].{{sfn|Kuehn|2001|p=26}} He was the fourth of nine children (six of whom reached adulthood).<ref>{{cite web |last=Haupt |first=Viktor |title=Rede des Bohnenkönigs – Von Petersburg bis Panama – Die Genealogie der Familie Kant |url=https://www.freunde-kants.com/kopie-von-kant-war-ostpreusse-1 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150925124214/http://www.freunde-kants.com/attachments/article/137/Bohnenrede%202015%20%28de%29.pdf |archive-date=25 September 2015 |website=freunde-kants.com |page=7 |language=de}}</ref> The Kant household stressed the [[Pietism|pietist]] values of religious devotion, humility, and a literal interpretation of the [[Bible]].<ref>{{Cite encyclopedia |last1=Pasternack |first1=Lawrence |title=Kant's Philosophy of Religion |date=2020 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/kant-religion/ |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |edition=Spring 2020 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=25 February 2021 |last2=Fugate |first2=Courtney}}</ref> Immanuel Kant's early education was strict, punitive, and highly disciplinary, with an emphasis on Latin and religious instruction rather than mathematics and science.<ref>Kuehn 2001, p. 47.</ref> In his later years, Kant lived a strictly ordered life. It was said that neighbors would set their clocks by his daily walks. Kant considered marriage two times, first a widow and then a [[Westphalia]]n girl, but both times waited too long.{{sfn|Kuehn|2001|p=177}} Though he never married, he seems to have had a rewarding social life; he was a popular teacher as well as a modestly successful author, even before starting on his major philosophical works.{{sfn|Kuehn|2001|p=169}}
==Biography==
====Birth and youth====
Immanuel Kant - who was baptized as "Emanuel" but later changed his name to "Immanuel" - was born in [[1724]] in [[Königsberg]], [[Germany]] (now [[Kaliningrad]], [[Russia]]). He spent his entire life in and around his hometown, the capital of [[East Prussia]] at that time. His father was a German craftsman from [[Memel]], Germany's northeasternmost city (now [[Klaipėda]], [[Lithuania]]). In his youth, Kant was a solid, albeit unspectacular, student. He was raised in a [[Pietism|Pietist]] household, a then popular [[Lutheran]] reform movement that stressed intense religious devotion, personal humility and a literal reading of [[The Bible]]. Consequently, Kant received a stern education -- strict, punitive, and disciplinary -- that favored Latin and religious instruction over mathematics and science. Kant later described this period as a time of unhappiness. He then took a huge dump.
 
====The youngYoung scholar====
Kant showed a great aptitude for study at an early age. He first attended the [[Collegium Fridericianum]], from which he graduated at the end of the summer of 1740. In 1740, aged 16, he enrolled at the [[University of Königsberg]], where he would later remain for the rest of his professional life.<ref>''The American International Encyclopedia'' (New York: J.J. Little & Ives, 1954), Vol. IX.</ref> He studied the philosophy of [[Gottfried Leibniz]] and [[Christian Wolff (philosopher)|Christian Wolff]] under [[Martin Knutzen]] (Associate Professor of Logic and Metaphysics from 1734 until he died in 1751), a [[rationalism|rationalist]] who was also familiar with developments in British philosophy and science and introduced Kant to the new mathematical physics of [[Isaac Newton]]. Knutzen dissuaded Kant from the theory of [[pre-established harmony]], which he regarded as "the pillow for the lazy mind".<ref>{{cite book|title=What the Tortoise Taught Us: The Story of Philosophy|url=https://archive.org/details/whattortoisetaug00port|url-access=limited|last=Porter|first=Burton|publisher=Rowman & Littlefield Publishers|year=2010|page=[https://archive.org/details/whattortoisetaug00port/page/n145 133]}}</ref> He also dissuaded Kant from [[idealism]], the idea that reality is purely mental, which most philosophers in the 18th century regarded negatively. The theory of [[transcendental idealism]] that Kant later included in the ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'' was developed partially in opposition to traditional idealism. Kant had contacts with students, colleagues, friends and diners who frequented the local [[Masonic lodge]].<ref>{{cite web|url=https://library.oapen.org/bitstream/id/9c2c6b4d-7481-4e73-b443-bf29054680c2/497779.pdf|title=Die Freimaurer im Alten Preußen 1738–1806|language=de|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20201119104900/https://library.oapen.org/bitstream/id/9c2c6b4d-7481-4e73-b443-bf29054680c2/497779.pdf|archive-date=19 November 2020|url-status=live}}</ref>
Kant enrolled in the University of Königsberg in [[1740]], at the age of 16. He studied the philosophy of [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]] and [[Christian Wolff (philosopher)|Wolff]] under [[Martin Knutsen]], a [[rationalism|rationalist]] who was also familiar with the developments of British philosophy and science and who introduced Kant to the new mathematical physics of [[Isaac Newton|Newton]]. His father's stroke and subsequent death in [[1746]] interrupted his studies. Kant became a private tutor in the smaller towns surrounding Königsberg, but continued his scholarly research. [[1749]] saw the publication of his first philosophical work, ''[[Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces]]''. Kant published several more works on scientific topics and became a university lecturer in [[1755]]. From this point on, Kant turned increasingly to philosophical issues, although he would continue to write on the sciences throughout his life. In the early 1760s, Kant produced a series of important works in philosophy. ''[[The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures]]'', a work in logic, was published in [[1762]]. Two more works appeared the following year: ''[[Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy]]'' and ''[[The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God]]''. In [[1764]], Kant wrote ''[[Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime]]'' and then was second to [[Moses Mendelssohn]] in a Berlin Academy prize competition with his ''[[Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality]]'' (often referred to as "the Prize Essay"). In [[1770]], at the age of 45, Kant was finally appointed Professor of Logic and Metaphysics at the University of Königsberg. Kant wrote his ''[[Inaugural Dissertation]]'' in defense of this appointment. This work saw the emergence of several central themes of his mature work, including the distinction between the faculties of intellectual thought and sensible receptivity.
 
His father's stroke and subsequent death in 1746 interrupted his studies. Kant left Königsberg shortly after August 1748;{{sfn|Kuehn|2001|p=94}} he would return there in August 1754.{{sfn|Kuehn|2001|p=98}} He became a private tutor in the towns surrounding Königsberg, but continued his scholarly research. In 1749, he published his first philosophical work, ''[[Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces]]'' (written in 1745–1747).<ref>[[Eric Watkins (philosopher)|Eric Watkins]] (ed.), ''Immanuel Kant: Natural Science'', Cambridge University Press, 2012: [http://assets.cambridge.org/97805213/63945/excerpt/9780521363945_excerpt.pdf "Thoughts on the true estimation..."] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160307213516/http://assets.cambridge.org/97805213/63945/excerpt/9780521363945_excerpt.pdf |date=7 March 2016 }}.</ref>
====The critical turn====
At the age of 46, Kant was an established scholar and an increasingly influential philosopher. Much was expected of him. In response to a letter from his student, [[Markus Herz]], Kant came to recognize that in the ''[[Inaugural Dissertation]]'', he had failed to account for the relation and connection between our sensible and intellectual faculties. He also credited [[David Hume]] with awakening him from "dogmatic slumber" (circa 1770). Kant would not publish another work in philosophy for the next eleven years.
 
== Early work ==
Kant spent his silent decade working on a solution to the problems posed. When he emerged from his silence in [[1781]], the result was the ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]''. Although now uniformly recognized as one of the greatest works in the history of philosophy, this ''Critique'' was largely ignored upon its initial publication. The book was long, over 800 pages in the original German edition, and written in a dry, scholastic style. It received few reviews, and these failed to recognize the ''Critique'''s revolutionary nature. Kant was disappointed with the work's reception. Recognizing the obscurity of the original treatise, he wrote the ''[[Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics]]'' in [[1783]] as a summary of its main views and he encouraged his friend, [[Johann Schultz]], to publish a brief commentary of the ''Critique of Pure Reason''.
Kant is best known for his work in the philosophy of ethics and metaphysics, but he made significant contributions to other disciplines. In 1754, while contemplating on a prize question by the [[Prussian Academy of Sciences|Berlin Academy]] about the problem of Earth's rotation, he argued that the Moon's gravity would slow down Earth's spin and he also put forth the argument that gravity would eventually cause the Moon's [[tidal locking]] to [[orbital resonance|coincide]] with the Earth's rotation.{{efn|Kant himself seems to have found his contribution not significant enough that he published his arguments in a newspaper commentary on the prize question and did not submit them to the Academy: {{cite book|chapter-url=https://archive.org/details/in.ernet.dli.2015.54018/page/n113/mode/2up|chapter=Whether the Earth has Undergone an Alteration of its Axial Rotation|title=Kant's Cosmogony|translator-last=Hastie|translator-first=William|___location=Glasgow|publisher=James Maclehose|orig-date=1754|year=1900|pages=1–11|access-date=29 March 2022}}. The prize was instead awarded in 1756 to P. Frisi, who incorrectly argued against the slowing down of the spin.<ref>{{cite book |last=Schönfeld |first=Martin |title=The Philosophy of the Young Kant: The Precritical Project |publisher=Oxford University Press |page=84 |isbn=978-0195132182 |year=2000 }}</ref>}}<ref name="nebulous">{{cite book|last=Brush|first=Stephen G.|title=A History of Modern Planetary Physics: Nebulous Earth|year=2014|isbn=978-0521441711|page=[https://archive.org/details/historyofmodernp0000brus/page/7 7]|publisher=Cambridge University Press |url=https://archive.org/details/historyofmodernp0000brus/page/7}}</ref> The next year, he expanded this reasoning to the [[formation and evolution of the Solar System]] in his ''[[Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens]]''.<ref name="nebulous"/> In 1755, Kant received a license to lecture in the University of Königsberg and began lecturing on a variety of topics including mathematics, physics, logic, and metaphysics. In his 1756 essay on the theory of winds, Kant laid out an original insight into the [[Coriolis force]].{{Citation needed|date=August 2025}}
 
In 1756, Kant also published three papers on the [[1755 Lisbon earthquake]].<ref>See:
Kant's reputation gradually rose through the [[1780]]s, sparked by a series of important works: the [[1784]] essay, "[[What is Enlightenment?|Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?]]"; [[1785|1785's]] ''[[Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals]]'' (his first work on moral philosophy); and, from [[1786]], ''[[Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science]]''. But Kant's fame ultimately arrived from an unexpected source. In [[1786]], [[Karl Reinhold]] began to publish a series of public letters on the Kantian philosophy. In these letters, Reinhold framed Kant's philosophy as a response to the central intellectual controversy of the era: the [[Pantheism Dispute]]. [[Friedrich Jacobi]] had accused the recently deceased [[Lessing]] (a distinguished philosopher of the period) of [[Spinozism]]. Such a charge, tantamount to atheism, was vigorously denied by Lessing's friend [[Moses Mendelssohn]], and a bitter public dispute arose between them. The controversy gradually escalated into a general debate over the values of the Enlightenment and of reason itself. Reinhold maintained in his letters that Kant's ''Critique of Pure Reason'' could settle this dispute by defending the authority and bounds of reason. Reinhold's letters were widely read and made Kant the most famous philosopher of his era.
* Kant, I. (1756a) [https://babel.hathitrust.org/cgi/pt?id=umn.31951001073880s;view=1up;seq=448 "Von den Ursachen der Erderschütterungen bei Gelegenheit des Unglücks, welches die westliche Länder von Europa gegen das Ende des vorigen Jahres betroffen hat"] [On the causes of the earthquakes on the occasion of the disaster which affected the western countries of Europe towards the end of last year] In: Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften (Royal Prussian Academy of Sciences), ed.s (1902) ''Kant's gesammelte Schriften'' [Kant's collected writings] (in German) Berlin, Germany: G. Reimer. vol. 1, pp. 417–427.
* Kant, I. (1756b) [https://babel.hathitrust.org/cgi/pt?id=umn.31951001073880s;view=1up;seq=460 "Geschichte und Naturbeschreibung der merkwürdigsten Vorfälle des Erdbebens, welches an dem Ende des 1755sten Jahres einen großen Theil der Erde erschüttert hat"] [History and description of the nature of the most remarkable events of the earthquake which shook a large part of the Earth at the end of the year 1755], ibid. pp. 429–461.
* Kant, I. (1756c) [https://babel.hathitrust.org/cgi/pt?id=umn.31951001073880s;view=1up;seq=494 "Immanuel Kants fortgesetzte Betrachtung der seit einiger Zeit wahrgenommenen Erderschütterungen"] [Immanuel Kant's continued consideration of the earthquakes that were felt some time ago], ibid. pp. 463–472.
* Amador, Filomena (2004) "The causes of 1755 Lisbon earthquake on Kant" In: Escribano Benito, J.J.; Español González, L.; Martínez García, M.A., ed.s. ''Actas VIII Congreso de la Sociedad Española de Historia de las Ciencias y de las Técnicas'' [Proceedings of the Eighth Congress of the Spanish Society of the History of the Sciences and Technology] (in English) Logroño, Spain: Sociedad Española de Historia de las Ciencias y de las Técnicas (Universidad de la Rioja), vol. 2, pp. 485–495.</ref> Kant's theory, which involved shifts in huge caverns filled with hot gases, though inaccurate, was one of the first systematic attempts to explain earthquakes in natural rather than supernatural terms. In 1757, Kant began lecturing on geography, making him one of the first lecturers to explicitly teach geography as its own subject.<ref name="Richards-1974">{{Cite journal|last=Richards|first=Paul|date=1974|title=Kant's Geography and Mental Maps|journal=Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers|issue=61|pages=1–16|doi=10.2307/621596|jstor=621596| issn=0020-2754 }}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal|last=Elden|first=Stuart|date=2009|title=Reassessing Kant's geography|journal=Journal of Historical Geography|language=en|volume=35|issue=1|pages=3–25|doi=10.1016/j.jhg.2008.06.001|url=http://dro.dur.ac.uk/6836/1/6836.pdf|access-date=27 September 2019|archive-date=1 August 2020|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200801205430/http://dro.dur.ac.uk/6836/1/6836.pdf|url-status=live}}</ref> Geography was one of Kant's most popular lecturing topics and, in 1802, a compilation by Friedrich Theodor Rink of Kant's lecturing notes, ''Physical Geography'', was released. After Kant became a professor in 1770, he expanded the topics of his lectures to include lectures on [[natural law]], ethics, and [[anthropology]], along with other topics.<ref name="Richards-1974" />
 
[[File:Kant wohnhaus 2.jpg|thumb|Kant's house in Königsberg in an 1842 painting]]
====Kant's later work====
In the ''Universal Natural History'', Kant laid out the [[nebular hypothesis]], in which he deduced that the [[Solar System]] had formed from a large cloud of gas, a [[nebula]]. Kant also correctly deduced that the [[Milky Way]] was a [[galaxy|large disk of stars]], which he theorized formed from a much larger spinning gas cloud. He further suggested that other distant "nebulae" might be other galaxies. These postulations opened new horizons for astronomy, for the first time extending it beyond the solar system to galactic and intergalactic realms.<ref>{{cite book|last=Gamow|first=George|title=One Two Three... Infinity|___location=New York|publisher=Viking P.|date=1947|pages=300ff|title-link=One Two Three... Infinity}}</ref>
[[Image:Immanuel Kant (portrait).jpg|thumb|Immanuel Kant, detail from a 1791 watercolour by Gottlieb Doeppler]]
 
From then on, Kant turned increasingly to philosophical issues, although he continued to write on the sciences throughout his life. In the early 1760s, he produced a series of important works in philosophy. ''[[The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures]]'', a work in logic, was published in 1762. Two more works appeared the following year: ''Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy'' and ''[[The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God]]''. By 1764, Kant had become a notable popular author, and wrote ''[[Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime]]''; he was second to [[Moses Mendelssohn]] in a Berlin Academy prize competition with his ''Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality'' (often referred to as "The Prize Essay"). In 1766 Kant wrote a critical piece on [[Emanuel Swedenborg]]'s ''Dreams of a Spirit-Seer''.
Kant published a second edition of the ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'' in [[1787]], heavily revising the first parts of the book. Most of his subsequent work focused on other areas of philosophy. He continued to develop his moral philosophy, notably in [[1788]]'s ''[[Critique of Practical Reason]]'' (known as the second ''Critique'') and [[1797|1797's]] ''[[Metaphysics of Morals]]''. The [[1790]] ''[[Critique of Judgment]]'' (the third ''Critique'') applied the Kantian system to aesthetics and [[teleology]]. He also wrote a number of semi-popular essays on history, religion, politics and other topics. These works were well received by Kant's contemporaries and confirmed his preeminent status in eighteenth century philosophy. There were several journals devoted solely to defending and criticizing the Kantian philosophy. But despite his success, philosophical trends were moving in another direction. Many of Kant's most important disciples (including [[Karl Leonhard Reinhold|Reinhold]], [[Jakob Sigismund Beck|Beck]] and [[Fichte]]) transformed the Kantian position into increasingly radical forms of idealism. This marked the emergence of [[German Idealism]]. Kant was against these developments and publicly denounced Fichte in an open letter in [[1799]]. It was one of his final philosophical acts. Kant's health, long poor, turned for the worst and he died in [[1804]]. His unfinished final work, the fragmentary ''[[Opus Postumum]]'', was (as its title suggests) published posthumously. <!-- Where did he die? -->
 
In 1770, Kant was appointed Full Professor of Logic and Metaphysics at the University of Königsberg. In defense of this appointment, Kant wrote his [[inaugural dissertation]] ''On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and the Intelligible World''.{{efn|Since he had written his last [[habilitation thesis]] 14 years earlier, a new habilitation thesis was required (see S.J. McGrath, Joseph Carew (eds.), ''Rethinking German Idealism'', Palgrave Macmillan, 2016, p. 24).}} This work saw the emergence of several central themes of his mature work, including the distinction between the faculties of intellectual thought and sensible receptivity. To miss this distinction would mean to commit the error of [[subreption]], and, as he says in the last chapter of the dissertation, only in avoiding this error does metaphysics flourish.
====Erroneous beliefs====
A variety of popular beliefs have arisen concerning Kant's biography and legend. It is often held, for instance, that Kant was a late bloomer, that he only became an important philosopher in his mid-50s after rejecting his earlier views. While it is true that Kant wrote his greatest works relatively late in life, there is a tendency to underestimate the value of his earlier works. Recent Kant scholarship has devoted more attention to these "pre-critical" writings and has recognized a degree of continuity with his mature work.
 
While it is true that Kant wrote his greatest works relatively late in life, there is a tendency to underestimate the value of his earlier works. Recent Kant scholarship has devoted more attention to these "pre-critical" writings and has recognized a degree of continuity with his mature work.<ref>Cf., for example, Susan Shell, ''The Embodiment of Reason'' (Chicago, 1996)</ref>
Another common myth concerns Kant's personal mannerisms. It is often held that Kant lived a very strict and predictable life, leading to the oft-repeated story that neighbors would set their clocks by his daily walks. Again, this is only partly true. While still young, Kant was very gregarious and, though he never married, he remained fond of dinner parties through most of his life. Only later in his life, under the influence of his friend, the English merchant [[Joseph Green (18th century)|Joseph Green]], did Kant adopt a more regulated lifestyle{{fact}}.
 
===Publication of the ''Critique of Pure Reason''===
==Kant's moral philosophy==
{{Main|Critique of Pure Reason}}
[[Image:Immanuel Kant.jpg|right|thumb|Immanuel Kant]]
[[File:Painting of David Hume.jpg|thumb|The philosopher [[David Hume]] by [[Allan Ramsay (artist)|Allan Ramsay]]]]
Kant developed his moral philosophy in three works: ''[[Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals]]'' [http://eserver.org/philosophy/kant/metaphys-of-morals.txt] ([[1785]]), ''[[Critique of Practical Reason]]'' [http://eserver.org/philosophy/kant/critique-of-practical-reaso.txt] ([[1788]]), and ''Metaphysics of Morals'' [http://eserver.org/philosophy/kant/intro-to-metaphys-of-morals.txt] ([[1798]]).
At age 46, Kant was an established scholar and an increasingly influential philosopher, and much was expected of him. In correspondence with his ex-student and friend [[Markus Herz]], Kant admitted that, in the inaugural dissertation, he had failed to account for the relation between our sensible and intellectual faculties.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Watkins|first=Erik|title=Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: Background Source Materials|___location=Cambridge|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=2009|isbn=978-0521781626|page=276}}</ref> He needed to explain how we combine what is known as sensory knowledge with the other type of knowledge{{mdash}}that is, reasoned knowledge{{mdash}}these two being related but having very different processes. Kant also credited [[David Hume]] with awakening him from a "{{vanchor|dogmatic slumber}}" in which he had unquestioningly accepted the tenets of both religion and [[natural philosophy]].<ref name="Smith-1952">{{cite book|last=Smith|first=Homer W.|url=https://archive.org/details/manhisgods00smit|title=Man and His Gods|___location=New York|publisher=[[Grosset & Dunlap]]|year=1952|page=[https://archive.org/details/manhisgods00smit/page/404 404]|author-link=Homer W. Smith|url-access=registration}}</ref><ref>Kant, ''PFM'' 4:260</ref> Hume, in his 1739 ''[[Treatise on Human Nature]]'', had argued that people know the mind only through a subjective, essentially illusory series of perceptions. Ideas such as [[causality]], [[morality]], and [[Object (philosophy)|objects]] are not evident in experience, so their reality may be questioned. Kant felt that reason could remove this skepticism, and he set himself to solving these problems. Although fond of company and conversation with others, Kant isolated himself, and resisted friends' attempts to bring him out of his isolation.{{efn|In 1778, in response to one of these offers by a former pupil, Kant wrote: "Any change makes me apprehensive, even if it offers the greatest promise of improving my condition, and I am persuaded by this natural instinct of mine that I must take heed if I wish that the threads which the Fates spin so thin and weak in my case to be spun to any length. My great thanks, to my well-wishers and friends, who think so kindly of me as to undertake my welfare, but at the same time a most humble request to protect me in my current condition from any disturbance."<ref>Christopher Kul-Want and Andrzej Klimowski, ''Introducing Kant'' (Cambridge: Icon Books, 2005).{{page needed|date=October 2011}} {{ISBN|978-1840466645}}</ref>}} When Kant emerged from his silence in 1781, the result was the ''Critique of Pure Reason'', printed by [[Johann Friedrich Hartknoch]]. Kant countered Hume's [[empiricism]] by claiming that some knowledge exists inherently in the mind, independent of experience.<ref name="Smith-1952" /> He drew a parallel to the [[Copernican Revolution#Immanuel Kant|Copernican revolution]] in his proposal that worldly objects can be intuited ''[[A priori and a posteriori|a priori]]'', and that [[Anschauung|intuition]] is consequently distinct from [[Objectivity (philosophy)|objective reality]]. Perhaps the most direct contested matter was Hume's argument against any necessary connection between causal events, which Hume characterized as the "cement of the universe". In the ''Critique of Pure Reason'', Kant argues for what he takes to be the ''a priori'' justification of such necessary connection.<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' A188-211/B233-56</ref>
[[File:Immanuel Kant by Johann Christoph Frisch.jpg|left|thumb|Portrait of Kant by [[Johann Christoph Frisch]], after Johann Gottlieb Becker, {{circa|1770}}]]
Although now recognized as one of the greatest works in the history of philosophy, the ''Critique'' disappointed Kant's readers upon its initial publication.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Dorrien|first=Gary|title=Kantian Reason and Hegelian Spirit: The Idealistic Logic of Modern Theology|publisher=John Wiley & Sons|year=2012|isbn=978-0470673317|___location=Malden, MA|page=37}}</ref> The book was long, over 800 pages in the original German edition, and written in a convoluted style. Kant was quite upset with its reception.{{sfn|Kuehn|2001|pp=250–254}} His former student [[Johann Gottfried Herder]] criticized it for placing reason as an entity worthy of criticism by itself instead of considering the process of reasoning within the context of language and one's entire personality.<ref>[[Frederick Copleston|Copleston, Frederick Charles]] (2003). ''The Enlightenment: Voltaire to Kant''. p. 146.</ref> Similarly to [[Christian Garve]] and [[Johann Georg Heinrich Feder]], he rejected Kant's position that space and time possess a form that can be analyzed. Garve and Feder also faulted the ''Critique'' for not explaining differences in perception of sensations.<ref>Sassen, Brigitte. ''Kant's Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy''. 2000.</ref> Its density made it, as Herder said in a letter to [[Johann Georg Hamann]], a "tough nut to crack", obscured by "all this heavy gossamer".<ref>''Ein Jahrhundert deutscher Literaturkritik'', vol. III, ''Der Aufstieg zur Klassik in der Kritik der Zeit'' (Berlin, 1959), p. 315; as quoted in Gulyga, Arsenij. ''Immanuel Kant: His Life and Thought''. Trans. Marijan Despaltović. Boston: Birkhäuser, 1987.</ref> Its reception stood in stark contrast to the praise Kant had received for earlier works, such as his ''Prize Essay'' and shorter works that preceded the first ''Critique''. Recognizing the need to clarify the original treatise, Kant wrote the ''[[Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics]]'' in 1783 as a summary of its main views. Shortly thereafter, Kant's friend Johann Friedrich Schultz (1739–1805), a professor of mathematics, published ''Explanations of Professor Kant's Critique of Pure Reason'' (Königsberg, 1784), which was a brief but very accurate commentary on Kant's ''Critique of Pure Reason''.{{sfn|Kuehn|2001|pp=268–269}}
 
Kant's reputation gradually rose through the latter portion of the 1780s, sparked by a series of important works: the 1784 essay, "[[Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?]]"; 1785's ''[[Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals]]'' (his first work on moral philosophy); and ''[[Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science]]'' from 1786. Kant's fame ultimately arrived from an unexpected source. In 1786, [[Karl Leonhard Reinhold]] published a series of public letters on Kantian philosophy. In these letters, Reinhold framed Kant's philosophy as a response to the central intellectual controversy of the era: the [[pantheism controversy]]. [[Friedrich Jacobi]] had accused the recently deceased [[Gotthold Ephraim Lessing]] (a distinguished dramatist and philosophical essayist) of [[Spinozism]]. Such a charge, tantamount to an accusation of atheism, was vigorously denied by Lessing's friend [[Moses Mendelssohn]], leading to a bitter public dispute among partisans. The controversy gradually escalated into a debate about the values of the Enlightenment and the value of reason. Reinhold maintained in his letters that Kant's ''Critique of Pure Reason'' could settle this dispute by defending the authority and bounds of reason. Reinhold's [[Letter (message)|letters]] were widely read and made Kant the most famous philosopher of his era.<ref>{{Cite book|last=Guyer|first=Paul|title=The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=2006|isbn=978-0521823036|___location=Cambridge, UK|page=631}}</ref>
The three works proceed by a method of taking the "rational [, obvious, and everyday] knowledge of the moral to the philosophical [knowledge of the moral]" in the ''Groundwork'' - and also making necessary the moral works that followed; and then, in those latter works, following a method of using "practical reason", based only upon things about which reason can tell us, and not deriving any principles from experience, to reach conclusions which are able to be applied the world of experience (in the second part of ''The Metaphysic of Morals'').
 
== Later work ==
Kant is known for his theory that there is a single moral obligation, which he called the [[Categorical Imperative]], which is derived from the concept of duty. It is from the Categorical Imperative that all other moral obligations are generated, and by which all moral obligations can be tested. He believed that the moral law is a principle of [[reason]] itself, and is not based on contingent facts about the world, such as what would make us happy. Accordingly, he believed that moral obligation applies to all and only rational agents.
Kant published a second edition of the ''Critique of Pure Reason'' in 1787, heavily revising the first parts of the book. Most of his subsequent work focused on other areas of philosophy. He continued to develop his moral philosophy, notably in 1788's ''[[Critique of Practical Reason]]'' (known as the second ''Critique''), and 1797's ''[[Metaphysics of Morals]]''. The 1790 ''[[Critique of the Power of Judgment]]'' (the third ''Critique'') applied the Kantian system to aesthetics and [[teleology]]. In 1792, Kant's attempt to publish the Second of the four Pieces of ''[[Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason]]'',<ref name="KReligion">Werner S. Pluhar, ''[https://books.google.com/books?id=da8RrM-qkiwC&pg=PR7 Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200304020309/https://books.google.com/books?id=da8RrM-qkiwC&pg=PR7 |date=4 March 2020 }}''. 2009. [https://books.google.com/books?id=da8RrM-qkiwC Description] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200201192948/https://books.google.com/books/about/Religion_Within_the_Bounds_of_Bare_Reaso.html%3Fid%3Dda8RrM-qkiwC |date=1 February 2020 }} & [https://books.google.com/books?id=da8RrM-qkiwC&pg=PR7 Contents.] With an [https://books.google.com/books?id=da8RrM-qkiwC&pg=PR15 Introduction] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200803085237/https://books.google.com/books?id=da8RrM-qkiwC&pg=PR15 |date=3 August 2020 }} by Stephen Palmquist. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company,</ref> in the journal ''Berlinische Monatsschrift'', met with opposition from [[Frederick William II of Prussia|the King]]'s [[censorship]] commission, which had been established that same year in the context of the [[French Revolution]]. Kant then arranged to have all four pieces published as a book, routing it through the philosophy department at the University of Jena to avoid the need for theological censorship. This insubordination earned him a now-famous reprimand from the King. When he nevertheless published a second edition in 1794, the censor was so irate that he arranged for a royal order that required Kant never to publish or even speak publicly about religion. Kant then published his response to the King's reprimand and explained himself in the preface of ''The Conflict of the Faculties'' (1798).
 
[[File:Kant doerstling2.jpg|thumb|Kant with friends, including [[Christian Jakob Kraus]], [[Johann Georg Hamann]], [[Theodor Gottlieb von Hippel the Elder|Theodor Gottlieb von Hippel]], and [[Karl Gottfried Hagen]]]]
A categorical imperative is an unconditional obligation; that is, it has the force of an obligation regardless of our will or desires. (Contrast this with [[hypothetical imperative]].) Kant's categorical imperative was formulated in three ways, which he believed to be roughly equivalent (although many commentators do not):
He also wrote a number of semi-popular essays on history, religion, politics, and other topics. These works were well received by Kant's contemporaries and confirmed his preeminent status in eighteenth-century philosophy. There were several journals devoted solely to defending and criticizing Kantian philosophy. Despite his success, philosophical trends were moving in another direction. Many of Kant's most important disciples and followers (including [[Karl Leonhard Reinhold]], [[Jakob Sigismund Beck]], and [[Johann Gottlieb Fichte]]) transformed the Kantian position. The progressive stages of revision of Kant's teachings marked the emergence of [[German idealism]]. In what was one of his final acts expounding a stance on philosophical questions, Kant opposed these developments and publicly denounced Fichte in an open letter in 1799.<ref name="Fichte">{{cite web|url=http://www.korpora.org/Kant/aa12/370.html|title=Open letter by Kant denouncing Fichte's Philosophy|language=de|website=Korpora.org|access-date=24 July 2009|archive-date=19 July 2011|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110719150635/http://www.korpora.org/Kant/aa12/370.html|url-status=live}}</ref>
 
In 1800, a student of Kant named Gottlob Benjamin Jäsche (1762–1842) published a manual of logic for teachers called ''Logik'', which he had prepared at Kant's request. Jäsche prepared the ''Logik'' using a copy of a textbook in logic by [[Georg Friedrich Meier]] entitled ''Excerpt from the Doctrine of Reason'', in which Kant had written copious notes and annotations. The ''Logik'' has been considered of fundamental importance to Kant's philosophy, and the understanding of it. The great 19th-century logician [[Charles Sanders Peirce]] remarked, in an incomplete review of [[Thomas Kingsmill Abbott]]'s English translation of the introduction to ''Logik'', that "Kant's whole philosophy turns upon his logic."<ref>Peirce, C.S., ''Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce'', v. 1, (HUP, 1960), 'Kant and his Refutation of Idealism' p. 15
*The first formulation (Formula of Universal Law) says: "Act as if the maxim of thy action were to become by thy will a universal [[law of nature]]."
</ref> Also, [[Robert S. Hartman]] and Wolfgang Schwarz wrote in the translators' introduction to their English translation of the ''Logik'', "Its importance lies not only in its significance for the ''Critique of Pure Reason'', the second part of which is a restatement of fundamental tenets of the ''Logic'', but in its position within the whole of Kant's work."<ref>Kant, Immanuel, ''Logic'', G.B. Jäsche (ed), R.S. Hartman, W. Schwarz (translators), Indianapolis, 1984, p. xv.</ref>
 
== Death and burial ==
*The second formulation (Formula of Humanity) says: "Act that you use humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a means."
Kant's health, long poor, worsened. He died at Königsberg on 12 February 1804, uttering ''Es ist gut'' ("It is good") before his death.<ref>Karl Vorländer, ''Immanuel Kant: Der Mann und das Werk'', Hamburg: Meiner, 1992, p. II 332.</ref> His unfinished final work was published as ''[[Opus Postumum]]''. Kant always cut a curious figure in his lifetime for his modest, rigorously scheduled habits, which have been referred to as clocklike. [[Heinrich Heine]] observed the magnitude of "his destructive, world-crushing thoughts" and considered him a sort of philosophical "executioner", comparing him to [[Maximilien Robespierre]] with the observation that both men "represented in the highest the type of provincial bourgeois. Nature had destined them to weigh coffee and sugar, but Fate determined that they should weigh other things and placed on the scales of the one a king, on the scales of the other a god."<ref>{{cite web |url=http://philosophy.uchicago.edu/resources/files/On%20Kant.pdf |title=Heine on Immanuel Kant |access-date=10 July 2015 |archive-date=23 November 2015 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20151123060538/http://philosophy.uchicago.edu/resources/files/On%20Kant.pdf |url-status=live }}</ref>
 
When his body was transferred to a new burial spot, his skull was measured during the exhumation and found to be larger than the average German male's with a "high and broad" forehead.<ref>''Examined Lives, From Socrates to Nietzsche'', James Miller p. 284</ref> His forehead has been an object of interest ever since it became well known through his portraits: "In Döbler's portrait and in Kiefer's faithful if expressionistic reproduction of it—as well as in many of the other late eighteenth- and early-nineteenth-century portraits of Kant—the forehead is remarkably large and decidedly retreating."<ref>Immanuel Kant and the Bo(a)rders of Art History Mark Cheetham, in ''The Subjects of Art History: Historical Objects in Contemporary Perspectives'', p. 16</ref>
*The third formulation (Formula of Autonomy) is a synthesis of the first two. It says that we should so act that we may think of ourselves as [[legislating]] universal laws through our maxims, in a possible [[Kingdom of Ends]].
 
[[File:Kaliningrad 05-2017 img05 Kant Island.jpg|upright|thumb|Kant's tomb in [[Kaliningrad]], Russia]]
===Example of the first formulation===
Kant's [[mausoleum]] adjoins the northeast corner of [[Königsberg Cathedral]] in [[Kaliningrad]], Russia. The mausoleum was constructed by the architect [[Friedrich Lahrs]] and was finished in 1924, in time for the bicentenary of Kant's birth. Originally, Kant was buried inside the cathedral, but in 1880 his remains were moved to a [[neo-Gothic]] chapel adjoining the northeast corner of the cathedral. Over the years, the chapel became dilapidated and was demolished to make way for the mausoleum, which was built on the same ___location. The tomb and its mausoleum are among the few artifacts of German times preserved by the [[Soviets]] after they captured the city.<ref>{{Cite news|url=http://www.spiegel.de/international/zeitgeist/architectural-competition-held-to-rebuild-koenigsberg-city-center-a-980260.html|title=Resurrecting Königsberg: Russian City Looks to German Roots|last=Beyer|first=Susanne|date=25 July 2014|work=Spiegel Online|access-date=3 February 2018|archive-date=4 February 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180204192755/http://www.spiegel.de/international/zeitgeist/architectural-competition-held-to-rebuild-koenigsberg-city-center-a-980260.html|url-status=live}}</ref>
The most popular interpretation of the first formulation is called the "universalizability test." An agent's maxim, according to Kant, is his "subjective principle of volition" &mdash; that is, what the agent believes is his reason to act. The universalizability test has five steps:
 
Into the 21st century, many newlyweds bring flowers to the mausoleum. Artifacts previously owned by Kant, known as ''Kantiana'', were included in the [[Königsberg City Museum]]; however, the museum was destroyed during [[World War II]]. A replica of the statue of Kant that in German times stood in front of the main [[University of Königsberg]] building was donated by a German entity in the early 1990s and placed in the same grounds. After [[Flight and expulsion of Germans (1944–1950)|the expulsion]] of Königsberg's German population at the end of World War II, the University of Königsberg where Kant taught was replaced by the Russian-language Kaliningrad State University, which appropriated the campus and surviving buildings. In 2005, the university was renamed Immanuel Kant State University of Russia.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Zieliński |first=Miłosz J. |date=2018 |title=Kant's Future: Debates about the Identity of Kaliningrad Oblast |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/26644305 |journal=Slavic Review |volume=77 |issue=4 |pages=937–956 |doi=10.1017/slr.2018.291 |jstor=26644305 |issn=0037-6779|url-access=subscription }}</ref> The name change, which was considered a politically-charged issue due to the residents having mixed feelings about its German past,<ref>{{cite news |date=2 July 2005 |title=Kaliningrad Struggles With German Legacy |url=https://www.dw.com/en/kaliningrad-struggles-with-german-legacy/a-1635700 |access-date=23 April 2024 |work=DW News }}</ref> was announced at a ceremony attended by Russian president [[Vladimir Putin]] and German chancellor [[Gerhard Schröder]],<!--http://en.kremlin.ru/events/president/news/33684/photos--><ref>{{cite news |last=Dempsey |first=Judy |date=1 July 2005 |title=Russian enclave lands in diplomatic donnybrook |url=https://www.nytimes.com/2005/07/01/world/europe/russian-enclave-lands-in-diplomatic-donnybrook.html |access-date=23 April 2024 |work=The New York Times |issn=0362-4331}}</ref><ref>{{cite news |date=3 July 2005 |title=Iran the Topic in Baltic Sea Meeting |url=https://www.dw.com/en/iran-the-topic-in-baltic-sea-meeting/a-1637921 |access-date=23 April 2024 |agency=Agence-France Press|via=DW News}}</ref><ref>{{cite news |last=Ypi |first=Lea |date=20 April 2024 |title=Kant and the case for peace |url=https://www.ft.com/content/c7432bdc-3449-421e-8045-701ac16a3d07 |access-date=23 April 2024 |website=Financial Times |issn=0307-1766}}</ref> and the university formed a Kant Society, dedicated to the study of [[Kantianism]]. In 2010, the university was again renamed to [[Immanuel Kant Baltic Federal University]].<ref>{{cite web |date=13 October 2010 |title=Executive order on establishing Immanuel Kant University |url=http://en.kremlin.ru/events/president/news/9234<!--http://eng.kremlin.ru/news/1131--> |access-date=23 April 2024 |website=President of Russia}}</ref>
# Find the agent's maxim. The maxim is an action paired with its motivation. Example: "I will lie for personal benefit." Lying is the action, the motivation is to get what you desire. Paired together they form the maxim.
# Imagine a possible world in which everyone in a similar position to the real-world agent followed that maxim.
# Decide whether any contradictions or irrationalities arise in the possible world as a result of following the maxim.
# If a contradiction or irrationality arises, acting on that maxim is not allowed in the real world.
# If there is no contradiction, then acting on that maxim is permissible, and in some instances required.
 
==Philosophy==
(For a modern parallel, see [[John Rawls]]' hypothetical situation, the [[original position]].)
{{main|Kantianism}}
[[File:Immanuel Kant by Emanuel Bardou, view 2, Berlin, 1798, marble - Bode-Museum - DSC02884.JPG|thumb|Bust of Kant by [[Emanuel Bardou]], 1798]]
Like many of his contemporaries, Kant was greatly impressed with the scientific advances made by [[Isaac Newton|Sir Isaac Newton]] and others. This new evidence of the power of human reason called into question for many the traditional authority of politics and religion. In particular, the modern mechanistic view of the world called into question the very possibility of morality; for, if there is no agency, there cannot be any responsibility.<ref>Kant ''CPuR'' Bxxviii–Bxxx</ref>{{sfn|di Giovanni|2005}}
 
The aim of Kant's critical project is to secure human autonomy, the basis of religion and morality, from this threat of mechanism—and to do so in a way that preserves the advances of modern science.{{sfn|Rohlf|2020|loc = §2.1}} In the ''Critique of Pure Reason'', Kant summarizes his philosophical concerns in the following three questions:
==Belief in God==
# What can I know?
Kant stated his belief in God in [[Critique of Pure Reason]] and made a moral argument for God although such arguments have been criticized. See [[Argument from morality]] for more details.
# What should I do?
# What may I hope?<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' A804–05/B833</ref>
The ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'' focuses upon the first question and opens a conceptual space for an answer to the second question. It argues that even though we cannot strictly ''know'' that we are free, we can—and for practical purposes, must—''think'' of ourselves as free. In Kant's own words, "I had to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith."<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' Bxxx</ref> Our rational faith in morality is further developed in the ''[[Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals]]'' and the ''[[Critique of Practical Reason]]''.{{sfn|Guyer|2014|pp=7–8}}{{sfn|Jankowiak|2023}}
 
The ''[[Critique of Judgment|Critique of the Power of Judgment]]'' argues we may ''rationally'' hope for the harmonious unity of the theoretical and practical domains treated in the first two ''Critiques'' on the basis, not only of its conceptual possibility, but also on the basis of our affective experience of natural beauty and, more generally, the organization of the natural world.{{sfn|Guyer|2014|pp=6–8}} In ''[[Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason|Religion within the Bounds of Mere Reason]]'', Kant endeavors to complete his answer to this third question.<ref>di Giovanni, George. (1996) "Translator's Introduction", In ''Religion and Rational Theology''. Cambridge University Press. p.49, citing Kant in correspondence with Stäudlin.</ref>
==Political philosophy==
Kant was an advocate of [[constitutional republicanism]]. He opposed democracy, believing that majority rule posed a threat to individual liberty. He says, "Democracy is necessarily despotism, as it establishes an executive power contrary to the general will; all being able to decide against one whose opinion may differ, the will of all is therefore not that of all: which is contradictory and opposite to liberty." (''Perpetual Peace, II, 1795'')
 
These works all place the active, rational human [[subject (philosophy)|subject]] at the center of the cognitive and moral worlds. In brief, Kant argues that the [[mind]] itself necessarily makes a constitutive contribution to [[knowledge]], that this contribution is transcendental rather than psychological, and that to act autonomously is to act according to rational moral principles.{{sfn|Rohlf|2020}}
==Influence==
Kant's most powerful and revolutionary effect on philosophy, which changed forever its meaning, modes of thinking, and language(s), was not "[[positivism|positive]]" in the sense of producing specific assertions about the world that have become accepted truths, as in the positive sciences. Rather it was "[[anti-positivism|negative]]" in the sense of restricting the areas about which such knowledge was possible &mdash; by making philosophy "critical" and self-critical. Kant's idea of "critique" was to examine the legitimate scope of the mind or of knowledge. In this regard the "critique of pure reason", which was also the title of his most important work (see below and [[Critique of Pure Reason]]), meant examining what certain and legitimate knowledge human beings could arrive at simply by thinking about things independently of experience and perception, with his conclusion being: not very much. Prior to Kant, the entire mode of functioning of most philosophy was drawing conclusions about the nature of the universe, of God, or of the soul simply by logical thinking about them, by what seemed to make sense through "a priori" thinking, i.e. thinking on purely logical grounds. For this sort of thinking it ''must'' be the case that God or the universe is this way or that way, because it makes sense logically. But, in the history of philosophy, for every philosophical theory that God or the universe or the mind ''must'' be one way, some philosopher arrived at another theory stating that it ''must'' be precisely the opposite way. Kant called this unproductive, unresolvable, back-and-forth, dogmatic thinking the "dialectic of pure reason". That is, it was an inevitable consequence of trying to arrive at knowledge on purely logical grounds independently of experience or of scientific knowledge based on the evidence of the senses. For Kant, this entire style of pursuing knowledge was bankrupt and must be abandoned. According to Kant, philosophy must henceforth operate within the narrow "limits of pure reason" and recognize that most positive knowledge could come only through the sciences based on sense perception and not through [[metaphysics]], which was about things of which we could never have direct sense perception.
 
===Kant's critical project===
The philosopher [[Arthur Schopenhauer]] was strongly influenced by Kant's [[transcendental idealism]]. Schopenhauer accepted the distinction between two kinds of [[knowledge]]: the world perceived as [[phenomenon]] and the world thought of as non-phenomenon ([[thing-in-itself]]). For Kant, the thing-in-itself cannot be an object of perceived experience. But, for Schopenhauer, the thing-in-itself can be directly and immediately experienced as the basis of that which, in animal life, is known as [[will]], [[desire]], striving, craving, or urging. Schopenhauer claimed that the will as such, as thing-in-itself, is the inner, essential nature of the whole experienced world.
{{See also|Critique of Pure Reason}}
[[File:Kant017.jpg|thumb|Kant by [[Carle Vernet]]]]
Some important philosophers and schools of thought, such as [[German Idealism|German Idealists]], [[neo-Thomists]] and other theologically oriented philosophers, and [[Heidegger]]'s "fundamental ontology" have refused to accept the limitations that Kant imposed upon philosophy and attempted to come up with new metaphysical systems about "the Absolute", "God", or "Being" , although even these philosophers have generally tried doing so by taking Kant into account. Over-all, however, post-Kantian philosophy has never been able to return to the style of thinking, arguing, and asserting conclusions that characterized philosophy before him. In this way, Kant was correct in asserting that he had brought about a "Copernican revolution" in philosophy. According to Kant, [[Copernicus]]'s revolution in the understanding of the [[cosmos]] lay in taking the position of the observer into account. This explained why it looks as though the sun revolves around the earth even though in reality the earth revolves around the sun. Taking the observer's position into account prevents the unaware projection of the observer's perception or point of view onto the picture of the universe. Kant saw his own Copernican revolution in philosophy, analogously, as consisting in taking the position of the knower into account and thereby preventing the unaware projection of the knower's way of thinking ("pure reason") onto the philosophical map of reality. According to Kant, it was philosophers unawarely doing this that had created the illusions of metaphysics that dominated the prior history of philosophy. Kant saw this revolution, in turn, as being part of "Enlightenment" (as conceived of in the [[Age of Enlightenment]]) and the creation of an enlightened citizenry and society freed from dogmatism and irrational authority.
 
Kant's 1781 (revised 1787) ''Critique of Pure Reason'' has often been cited as the most significant volume of metaphysics and [[epistemology]] in modern philosophy.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Rohlf |first=Michael |title=Immanuel Kant |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant/ |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20191114014720/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant/ |archive-date=14 November 2019 |access-date=29 May 2019 |website=[[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]}}</ref> In the first ''Critique'', and later on in other works as well, Kant frames the "general" and "real problem of pure reason" in terms of the following question: "How are synthetic judgments ''a priori'' possible?"<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' B135</ref>{{sfn|Guyer|2014|p=51}} To understand this claim, it is necessary to define some terms. First, Kant makes a distinction between two sources of knowledge:
Kant's wider influence not only in philosophy but in the humanities and social sciences generally lies in the central concept of the ''Critique of Pure Reason'', namely that it is the synthesizing, unifying, ''constitutive'' activity of the subject of knowledge that is at the basis of our having an ordered world of experience and of the objects of knowledge themselves. This idea has spread out through many intellectual disciplines in which it has manifested itself in different forms, for example:
:*from [[Marx]]'s notion, in [[social theory]], of the constitutive role of human [[Work|labor]] in the creation of [[history]] and [[society]]
:* through [[Freud]]'s notion, in [[psychology]], that the activity of the [[ego]] produces the [[reality principle]]
:* through [[Durkheim]]'s notion, in [[sociology]], that society creates [[collective consciousness]] through [[social category|social categories]]
:* through [[Noam Chomsky|Chomsky]]'s notion, in [[linguistics]], of [[transformational grammar]]
:* to current notions, in several of the [[humanities]] and [[social sciences]], regarding the "[[social construction of reality]]" ([[Peter L. Berger|Berger]] & [[Thomas Luckmann|Luckmann]], 1966).
In this way Kant's conception of synthesizing, ordering mental activity has become central to modern intellectual culture.
 
# Cognitions ''a priori'': "cognition independent of all experience and even of all the impressions of the senses".
==Tomb==
# Cognitions ''a posteriori'': cognitions that have their sources in experience{{mdash}}that is, which are empirical.<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' B1–3</ref>
[[Image:Kant's tombstone Kaliningrad.jpeg|right|thumb|150px|The inscription upon Kant's tomb near the [[Kant Russian State University]].]]
 
Second, he makes a distinction in terms of the ''form'' of knowledge:
From [[1873]] to [[1881]], money was raised to build a monument chapel. His [[tomb]] and its [[pillar]]ed enclosure outside the Königsberg Cathedral in Kaliningrad, on the Pregolya (Pregel) River, are some of the few artifacts of German times preserved by the [[Soviets]] after they conquered the city in [[1945]]. Kant's original tomb was demolished by Russian bombs early in that year. A replica of a statue of Kant that stood in front of the university was donated by a German entity in 1991 and placed on the original pediment. Newlyweds bring flowers to the chapel, as they formerly did for Lenin's monument. Near his tomb is the following inscription in [[German language|German]] and [[Russian language|Russian]], taken from the "Conclusion" of his ''Critique of Practical Reason'': "Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and awe, the more often and steadily we reflect upon them: the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me."
 
# Analytic judgements: judgements in which the predicate concept is contained in the subject concept; e.g., "All bachelors are unmarried", or "All bodies take up space". These can also be called "judgments of clarification".
==Bibliography==
# Synthetic judgements: judgements in which the predicate concept is not contained in the subject concept; e.g., "All bachelors are alone", "All swans are white", or "All bodies have weight". These can also be called "judgments of amplification".<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' A6–8/B10–12</ref>
* ([[1749]]) ''[[Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces]]'' (''Gedanken von der wahren Schätzung der lebendigen Kräfte'')
* ([[1755]]) ''[[Universal Natural History and Theory of Heaven]]'' (''Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und Theorie Des Himmels'' [http://www.mala.bc.ca/~johnstoi/kant2g.htm])
* ([[1762]]) ''[[The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures]]'' (''Die falsche Spitzfindigkeit der vier syllogistischen Figuren'')
* ([[1763]]) ''[[The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God]]'' (''Der einzig mögliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseins Gottes'')
* ([[1763]]) ''[[Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy]]'' (''Versuch den Begriff der negativen Größen in die Weltweisheit einzuführnen'')
* ([[1764]]) ''[[Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime]]'' (''Beobachtungen über das Gefühl des Schönen und Erhabenen'')
* ([[1764]]) ''[[Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality]]'' (the ''Prize Essay'') (''Untersuchungen über die Deutlichkeit der Grundsätze der natürlichen Theologie und der Moral'')
* ([[1770]]) ''[[Inaugural Dissertation]]'' (''De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis forma et principiis'')
* ([[1781]]) First edition of the ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'' [http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/cpr/toc.html] (''Kritik der reinen Vernunft'' [http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/krva/krva.htm])
* ([[1783]]) ''[[Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics]]'' [http://eserver.org/philosophy/kant-prolegomena.txt] (''Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik'')
* ([[1784]]) "[[What Is Enlightenment?|An Answer To The Question: What Is Enlightenment?]]" (''Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklärung?'' [http://www.prometheusonline.de/heureka/philosophie/klassiker/kant/aufklaerung.htm])
* ([[1784]]) ''[[Idea For A Universal History With A Cosmopolitan Purpose]]'' (''Idee zu einer allgemeinen Geschichte in weltbürgerlicher Absicht'')
* ([[1785]]) ''[[Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals]]'' (''Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten'')
* ([[1786]]) ''[[Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science]]'' (''Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft'')
* ([[1787]]) Second edition of the ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'' [http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/cpr/toc.html] (''Kritik der reinen Vernunft'' [http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/krvb/krvb.htm])
* ([[1788]]) ''[[Critique of Practical Reason]]'' [http://eserver.org/philosophy/kant/critique-of-practical-reaso.txt] (''Kritik der praktischen Vernunft'' [http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/kritikpr/kritikpr.htm])
* ([[1790]]) ''[[Critique of Judgment]]'' (''Kritik der Urteilskraft'' [http://wikisource.org/wiki/Kritik_der_Urteilskraft])
* ([[1790]]) ''[[The Science of Right]]'' [http://eserver.org/philosophy/kant/science-of-right.txt]
* ([[1793]]) ''[[Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone]]'' (''Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der bloßen Vernunft'') [http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/ethics/kant/religion/religion-within-reason.htm]
* ([[1795]]) ''[[Perpetual Peace]]'' [http://www.mtholyoke.edu/acad/intrel/kant/kant1.htm] (''Zum ewigen Frieden'' [http://www.uni-kassel.de/fb5/frieden/themen/Theorie/kant.html])
* ([[1797]]) ''[[Metaphysics of Morals]]'' (''Metaphysik der Sitten'')
* ([[1798]]) ''[[Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View]]'' (''Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht'')
* ([[1798]]) ''[[The Contest of Faculties]]'' [http://chnm.gmu.edu/revolution/d/564/] (''Der Streit der Fakultäten'' [http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/streit/streit.htm])
* ([[1800]]) ''[[Kant's Logik|Logic]]'' (''Logik'')
* ([[1803]]) ''[[On Pedagogy]]'' (''Über Pädagogik'' [http://www1.uni-bremen.de/~kr538/kantpaed.html])
* ([[1804]]) ''[[Opus Postumum]]''
* (More German works at [http://de.wikisource.org/wiki/Immanuel_Kant Wikisource])
* (More German works at [http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/autoren/kant.htm Project Gutenberg])
* (More English works at [http://etext.library.adelaide.edu.au/aut/kant_immanuel.html The University of Adelaide Library])
 
An analytic judgement is true by nature of strictly conceptual relations. All analytic judgements are ''a priori'' since basing an analytic judgement on experience would be absurd.<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' B11</ref> By contrast, a synthetic judgement is one the content of which includes something new in the sense that it is includes something not already contained in the subject concept. The truth or falsehood of a synthetic statement depends upon something more than what is contained in its concepts. The most obvious form of synthetic judgement is a simple empirical observation.{{sfn|Guyer|2014|pp=52–54}}
==See also==
{{Wikiquotepar|Immanuel Kant}}
{{commons|Immanuel Kant}}
{{wikisource author}}
*[[Kantianism]]
*[[Neo-Kantianism]]
*[[Liberalism]]
*[[Contributions to liberal theory]]
*[[Kant Russian State University]]
 
Philosophers such as [[David Hume]] believed that these were the only possible kinds of human reason and investigation, which Hume called "relations of ideas" and "matters of fact".<ref>Hume, David. ''An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding''. Section 4; Part 1.</ref> Establishing the synthetic ''a priori'' as a third mode of knowledge would allow Kant to push back against Hume's skepticism about such matters as causation and metaphysical knowledge more generally. This is because, unlike ''a posteriori'' cognition, ''a priori'' cognition has "true or strict ... universality" and includes a claim of "necessity".<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' B3–4</ref>{{sfn|Guyer|2014|pp=52–54}} Kant himself regards it as uncontroversial that we do have synthetic ''a priori'' knowledge{{mdash}}especially in mathematics. That 7 + 5 = 12, he claims, is a result not contained in the concepts of seven, five, and the addition operation.<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' B14–17</ref> Yet, although he considers the possibility of such knowledge to be obvious, Kant nevertheless assumes the burden of providing a philosophical proof that we have ''a priori'' knowledge in mathematics, the natural sciences, and metaphysics. It is the twofold aim of the ''Critique'' both ''to prove'' and ''to explain'' the possibility of this knowledge.{{sfn|Guyer|2014|p=55}} Kant says "There are two stems of human cognition, which may perhaps arise from a common but to us unknown root, namely sensibility and understanding, through the first of which objects are ''given'' to us, but through the second of which they are ''thought''."<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' A15/B29, emphases added</ref>
==References and further reading==
Any suggestion of further reading on Kant has to take cognizance of the fact that his work has dominated philosophy like no other figure after him. Nevertheless, several guideposts can be made out. In Germany, the most important contemporary interpreter of Kant and the movement of German Idealism which he began is Dieter Henrich, who has some work available in English. P.F. Strawson's "The Bounds of Sense" (1969) played a significant role in determing the contemporary reception of Kant in England and America. At the same time, many key features of his position have been widely rejected. More recent interpreters of note in the English-speaking world include Lewis White Beck, Jonathan Benett, Henry Allison, [[Paul Guyer]], Robert B Pippin, Rudolf Makkreel, and Béatrice Longuenesse.
 
Kant's term for the object of sensibility is intuition, and his term for the object of the understanding is concept. In general terms, the former is a non-discursive representation of a ''particular'' object, and the latter is a discursive (or mediate) representation of a ''general type'' of object.{{sfn|Guyer|2014|pp=32, 61}} The conditions of possible experience require both intuitions and concepts, that is, the affection of the receptive sensibility and the actively synthesizing power of the understanding.{{sfn|Rohlf|2020|loc=§2.12}}{{efn|More technically, Kant puts his general point that all genuine knowledge requires both sensory input and intellectual organization by saying that all knowledge requires both "intuitions" and "concepts" (e.g., A 50 / B 74). Intuitions and concepts are two different species of the genus "representation" (''Vorstellung''), Kant's most general term for any cognitive state (see A 320 / B 376–7). At the outset of the "Transcendental Aesthetic", Kant states that an "intuition" is our most direct or "immediate" kind of representation of objects, in contrast to a "concept" which always represents an object "through a detour (''indirecte'')"{{mdash}}that is, merely by some "mark" or property that the object has (A 19 / B 33). In his logic textbook, Kant defines an intuition as a "''singular'' representation"{{mdash}}that is, one that represents a particular object{{mdash}}while a concept is always a "''universal'' (''repraesentation per notas communes'')", which represents properties common to many objects (''Logic'', §1, 9:91).{{sfn|Guyer|2014|pp=60–61}}}} Thus the statement: "Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind."<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' A51/B75</ref> Kant's basic strategy in the first half of his book will be to argue that some intuitions and concepts are pure{{mdash}}that is, are contributed entirely by the mind, independent of anything empirical. Knowledge generated on this basis, under certain conditions, can be synthetic ''a priori''. This insight is known as Kant's "Copernican revolution", because, just as Copernicus advanced astronomy by way of a radical shift in perspective, so Kant here claims do the same for metaphysics.<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' Bxvi–xviii</ref>{{sfn|Rohlf|2020|loc=§2.2}} The second half of the ''Critique'' is the explicitly ''critical'' part. In this "transcendental dialectic", Kant argues that many of the claims of traditional rationalist metaphysics violate the criteria he claims to establish in the first, "constructive" part of his book.{{sfn|Jankowiak|2023|loc=2(g)}}{{sfn|Guyer|2014|loc=ch. 4}} As Kant observes, however, "human reason, without being moved by the mere vanity of knowing it all, inexorably pushes on, driven by its own need to such questions that cannot be answered by any experiential use of reason".<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' B21</ref> It is the project of "the critique of pure reason" to establish the limits as to just how far reason may legitimately so proceed.<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' Axi–xii</ref>
===General introductions to Kant's thought===
*Broad C. D. ''Kant: An Introduction''. Cambridge University Press, 1978. ISBN 0521217555, ISBN 0521292654
 
=== Doctrine of transcendental idealism ===
===Biography and historical context===
{{See also | Transcendental idealism}}
*Beck, Lewis White. "Early German Philosophy: Kant and his Predecessors." Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1969.
The section of the ''Critique'' entitled "The transcendental aesthetic" introduces Kant's famous metaphysics of [[transcendental idealism]]. Something is "transcendental" if it is a necessary condition for the possibility of experience, and "idealism" denotes some form of mind-dependence that must be further specified. The correct interpretation of Kant's own specification remains controversial.{{sfn|Jankowiak|2023|loc= §2(d)}} The metaphysical thesis then states that human beings only experience and know phenomenal appearances, not independent things-in-themselves, because space and time are nothing but the subjective forms of intuition that we ourselves contribute to experience.{{sfn|Rohlf|2020|loc=§3}}<ref>Kant ''CPuR'' A43/B59–60, A369</ref> Nevertheless, although Kant says that space and time are "transcendentally ideal"—the ''pure forms'' of human sensibility, rather than part of nature or reality as it exists in-itself—he also claims that they are "empirically real", by which he means "that 'everything that can come before us externally as an object' is in both space and time, and that our internal intuitions of ourselves are in time".<ref>Kant ''CPuR'' A28/B44, A34–35/B51–51</ref>{{sfn|Rohlf|2020|loc=§3}} However Kant's doctrine is interpreted, he wished to distinguish his position from the [[subjective idealism]] of [[George Berkeley]].{{sfn|Stang|2022|loc=§2.3}}
::''a survey of Kant's intellectual background''
*Beiser, Frederick C. "The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte." Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987.
*Kuehn, Manfred. ''Kant: A Biography.'' Cambridge University Press, 2001. ISBN 0521497043
*Pinkard, Terry. ''German philosophy, 1760-1860: The Legacy of Idealism.'' Cambridge, 2002.
*Sassen, Brigitte. ed. ''Kant's Early Critics: The Empiricist Critique of the Theoretical Philosophy'', 2000.
 
[[Paul Guyer]], although critical of many of Kant's arguments in this section, writes of the "Transcendental Aesthetic" that it "not only lays the first stone in Kant's constructive theory of knowledge; it also lays the foundation for both his critique and his reconstruction of traditional metaphysics. It argues that all genuine knowledge requires a sensory component, and thus that metaphysical claims that transcend the possibility of sensory confirmation can never amount to knowledge."{{sfn|Guyer|2014|p=60}}
===Collections of essays===
*Guyer, Paul. ed. ''The Cambridge Companion to Kant.'' Cambridge University Press, 1992. ISBN 0521365872, ISBN 0521367689
::''an excellent collection of papers that covers most areas of Kant's thought''
*Mohanty, J.N. and Robert W. Shahan. eds. ''Essays on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.'' Norman : University of Oklahoma Press, 1982. ISBN 0806117826
*''Proceedings of the International Kant Congresses.'' Several Congresses (numbered) edited by various publishers.
*Förster, Eckart ed. "Kant's Transcendental Deductions: The Three 'Critiques' and the 'Opus Postumum.'" Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1989.
::''includes an important essay by Dieter Henrich'
*Cohen, Ted and Paul Guyer eds. ''Essays in Kant's Aesthetics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982.
::''essays on Kant's Critique of Judgment''
*Phillips, Dewi et al. ''Kant and Kierkegaard on Religion.'' Palgrave Macmillian, 2000, ISBN 0312232349
::''A collection of essays about Kantian religion and its influence on Kierkegaardian and contemporary philosophy of religion.''
 
====Interpretive disagreements====
===On Kant's theoretical philosophy===
One interpretation, known as the "two-world" interpretation, regards Kant's position as a statement of epistemological limitation, meaning that we are not able to transcend the bounds of our own mind, and therefore cannot access the "[[thing-in-itself]]". On this particular view, the thing-in-itself is not numerically identical to the phenomenal empirical object.<ref>{{cite book |last=Allison |first=Henry E. |title=Kant's Transcendental Idealism: An Interpretation and Defense |year=2004 |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn=978-0300102666 |pages=25–28}}</ref> Kant also spoke, however, of the thing-in-itself or ''transcendent object'' as a product of the (human) understanding as it attempts to conceive of objects in abstraction from the conditions of sensibility. Following this line of thought, a different interpretation argues that the thing-in-itself does not represent a separate ontological ___domain but simply a way of considering objects by means of the understanding alone; this is known as the "two-aspect" view.{{sfn|Rohlf|2020|loc = §§3.1–3.2}}{{sfn|Stang|2022|loc = §§4–5}} On this alternative view, the same objects to which we attribute empirical properties like color, size, and shape are also, when considered as they are in themselves, the things-in-themselves, otherwise inaccessible to human knowledge.<ref>{{cite book |last=Langton |first=Rae |title=Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves |year=1998 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0199243174|pages=105–107}}</ref>
*Allison, Henry. ''Kant’s Transcendental Idealism.'' New Haven : Yale University Press, 1983, 2004. ISBN 0300036299, ISBN 0300030029
::''very influential defense of Kant's idealism, recently revised''
*Ameriks, Karl. "Kant's Theory of Mind: An Analysis of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason." Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982.
::''one of the first detailed studies of the Dialectic in English''
*Gram, Moltke S. ''The Transcendental Turn: The Foundation of Kant's Idealism.'' Gainesville : University Presses of Florida, 1984. ISBN 0813007879
*Guyer, Paul. "Kant and the Claims of Knowledge." Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1987.
::''a modern defense of the view that Kant's theoretical philosophy is a "patchwork" of ill-fitting arguments''
*Henrich, Dieter. ''The Unity of Reason: Essays on Kant’s Philosophy.'' Edited and with an introduction by Richard L. Velkley ; translated by Jeffrey Edwards ... [et al.]. Harvard University Press, 1994. ISBN 0674929055
*Kemp Smith, Norman. "A Commentary to Kant's ‘Critique of Pure Reason.’" London: Macmillan, 1930.
::''a somewhat dated, but influential commentary on the first Critique, recently reprinted''
*Kitcher, Patricia. "Kant's Transcendental Psychology." New York: Oxford University Press, 1990.
*Longuenesse, Béatrice. ''Kant and the Capacity to Judge.'' Princeton University Press, 1998. ISBN 0691043485
::''argues that the notion of judgment provides the key to understanding the overall argument of the first Critique''
*Melnick, Arthur. "Kant's Analogies of Experience." Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973.
::''an important study of Kant's Analogies, including his defense of the principle of causality''
*Paton, H. J. "Kant’s Metaphysic of Experience: A Commentary on the First Half of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft." Two volumes. London: Macmillan, 1936.
::''an extensive study of Kant's theoretical philosophy''
*Pippin, Robert B. Kant's Theory of Form: An Essay on the Critique of Pure Reason. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1982.
::''an influential examination of the formal character of Kant's work''
*[[Arthur Schopenhauer]]: ''Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung. Erster Band. Anhang. Kritik der Kantischen Philosophie''. F. A. Brockhaus, Leipzig 1859 (In English: Arthur [[Schopenhauer]], New York: Dover Press, Volume I, Appendix, "[[Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy]]," ISBN 0-486-21761-2)
*Strawson, P.F. ''The Bounds of Sense: an essay on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.'' Routledge, 1989.
::''the work that revitalized the interest of contemporary analytic philosophers in Kant''
*Wolff, Robert Paul. ''Kant's theory of mental activity: A commentary on the transcendental analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason.'' Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1963.
::''a detailed and influential commentary on the first part of the Critique of Pure Reason''
 
===On Kant's practicaltheory of philosophyjudgment===
{{See also|Category (Kant)}}
*Banham, Gary. ''Kant's Practical Philosophy: From Critique to Doctrine'' Palgrave Macmillan, 2003.
[[File:Immanuelkant.JPG|thumb|Kant statue in the School of Philosophy and Human Sciences (FAFICH) in the Federal University of Minas Gerais (UFMG), [[Belo Horizonte]], Brazil]]
*Michalson, Gordon E. ''Fallen Freedom: Kant on Radical Evil and Moral Regeneration.'' Cambridge University Press, 1990.
*Michalson, Gordon E. ''Kant and the Problem of God.'' Blackwell Publishers, 1999.
*Rawls, John. ''Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy. '' Cambridge, 2000.
*Wolff, Robert Paul. ''The Autonomy of Reason: A Commentary on Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals.'' New York: HarperCollins, 1974. ISBN 0061317926.
 
Following the "Transcendental Analytic" is the "Transcendental Logic". Whereas the former was concerned with the contributions of the sensibility, the latter is concerned, first, with the contributions of the understanding ("Transcendental Analytic") and, second, with the faculty of ''reason'' as the source of both metaphysical errors and genuine regulatory principles ("Transcendental Dialectic"). The "Transcendental Analytic" is further divided into two sections. The first, "Analytic of Concepts", is concerned with establishing the universality and necessity of the ''pure'' concepts of the understanding (i.e., the categories). This section contains Kant's famous "transcendental deduction". The second, "Analytic of Principles", is concerned with the application of those pure concepts in ''empirical'' judgments. This second section is longer than the first and is further divided into many sub-sections.{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|pp=4–13}}
===On Kant's aesthetics===
*Guyer, Paul. ''Kant and the Claim of Taste''. Cambridge MA and London, 1979.
*Crawford, Donald. ''Kant's Aesthetic Theory''. Wisconsin, 1974.
*Makkreel, Rudolf, ''Imagination and Interpretation in Kant''. Chicago, 1990.
*McCloskey, Mary. ''Kant's Aesthetic.'' SUNY, 1987.
*Schaper, Eva. ''Studies in Kant's Aesthetics''. Edinburgh, 1979.
*Zupancic, Alenka. ''Ethics of the Real: Kant and Lacan''. Verso, 2000.
 
====Transcendental deduction of the categories of the understanding====
===Other work on Kant===
The "Analytic of Concepts" argues for the universal and necessary validity of the pure concepts of the understanding, or the categories, for instance, the concepts of substance and causation. These twelve basic categories define what it is to be a ''thing in general''{{mdash}}that is, they articulate the necessary conditions according to which something is a possible object of experience. These, in conjunction with the ''a priori'' forms of intuition, are the basis of all synthetic ''a priori'' cognition. According to [[Paul Guyer]] and [[Allen W. Wood]], "Kant's idea is that just as there are certain essential features of all judgments, so there must be certain corresponding ways in which we form the concepts of objects so that judgments may be about objects."{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|p=8}}
*Caygill, Howard. ''A Kant Dictionary''. Oxford, UK; Cambridge, Mass., USA : Blackwell Reference, 1995. ISBN 0631175342, ISBN 0631175350
 
Kant provides two central lines of argumentation in support of his claims about the categories. The first, known as the "metaphysical deduction", proceeds analytically from a table of the Aristotelian logical functions of judgment. As Kant was aware, this assumes precisely what the skeptic rejects, namely, the existence of synthetic ''a priori'' cognition. For this reason, Kant also supplies a synthetic argument that does not depend upon the assumption in dispute.{{sfn|Guyer|2014|pp=89–90}}
===Contemporary philosophy with a Kantian influence===
* Korsgaard, Christine. ''Creating the Kingdom of Ends.'' Cambridge ; New York, NY, USA : Cambridge University Press, 1996. ISBN 0521496446, ISBN 0521499623 (pbk.)
::''not a commentary, but a defense of a broadly Kantian approach to ethics''
* McDowell, John. ''Mind and World.'' Harvard University Press, 1994. ISBN 0674576098
::''offers a Kantian solution to a dilemma in contemporary epistemology regarding the relation between mind and world''
* Wood, Allen. ''Kant's Ethical Thought.'' Cambridge ; New York, NY, USA : Cambridge University Press, 1999. ISBN 052164836X
:: ''a comprehensive, in depth study of Kant's ethics, with emphasis on formula of humanity as most accurate formulation of the categorical imperative (according to similar arguments as Korsgaard)''
 
This argument, provided under the heading "Transcendental Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding", is widely considered to be both the most important and the most difficult of Kant's arguments in the ''Critique''. Kant himself said that it is the one that cost him the most labor.<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' Axi</ref> Frustrated by its confused reception in the first edition of his book, he rewrote it entirely for the second edition.{{sfn|Jankowiak|2023|loc= §2(e)}}{{sfn|Rohlf|2020|loc = §4}}
==External links==
*[http://ethics.acusd.edu/theories/kant Kant & Ethics]
*[http://naks.ucsd.edu/ North American Kant Society (NAKS)] (many helpful links!)
*[http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/Kant.html Kant on the Web]
*[http://comp.uark.edu/~rlee/semiau96/kantlink.html Kant Links]
*[http://www.friesian.com/kant.htm Epistemology and Metaphysics]
*[http://www.phil.upenn.edu/~cubowman/kant.html Kant and the project of enlightenment]
*[http://www.e-text.org/text/ Several Kant's works in clickable pdf]
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/contents.html#k Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (many entries on Kant)]
*{{gutenberg author|id=Kant, |name=Immanuel Kant}}
*[http://www.philos.msu.ru/community/staff/vasiliev/Kant_Interview/Kant_Interview.html International Kant Interview - 2004]
*[http://www.earlymoderntexts.com Readable versions of Prolegomena and Groundwork for Met.of Morals]
 
The "Transcendental Deduction" gives Kant's argument that these pure concepts apply universally and necessarily to the objects that are given in experience. According to Guyer and Wood, "He centers his argument on the premise that our experience can be ascribed to a single identical subject, via what he calls the 'transcendental unity of apperception,' only if the elements of experience given in intuition are synthetically combined so as to present us with objects that are thought through the categories."{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|p=9}}
{{Persondata
|NAME=Kant, Immanuel
|ALTERNATIVE NAMES=Kant, Emanuel
|SHORT DESCRIPTION=German philosopher
|DATE OF BIRTH=[[22 April]], [[1724]]
|PLACE OF BIRTH=[[Königsberg]]
|DATE OF DEATH=[[12 February]], [[1804]]
|PLACE OF DEATH=
}}
 
Kant's principle of apperception is that "The I think must be able to accompany all my representations; for otherwise something would be represented in me that could not be thought at all, which is as much as to say that the representation would either be impossible or else at least would be nothing for me."<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' B131-32</ref> The ''necessary'' possibility of the self-ascription of the representations of self-consciousness, identical to itself through time, is an ''a priori'' conceptual truth that cannot be based on experience.{{sfn|Rohlf|2020|loc = §4.1}} This is only a bare sketch of one of the arguments that Kant presents.
[[Category:1724 births|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:1804 deaths|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:Natives of Kaliningrad Oblast|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:18th century philosophers|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:Deontological ethics|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:Philosophers|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:Enlightenment philosophers|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:German philosophers|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:Idealists|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:Kantian philosophers|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:Kantianism]]
[[Category:Philosophers of law|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:Philosophy of sexuality|Kant, Immanuel]]
[[Category:Polymaths|Kant, Immanuel]]
 
====Principles of pure understanding====
{{Link FA|pl}}
Kant's deduction of the categories in the "Analytic of Concepts", if successful, demonstrates its claims about the categories only in an abstract way. The task of the "Analytic of Principles" is to show both ''that'' they must universally apply to objects given in actual experience (i.e., manifolds of intuition) and ''how'' it is they do so.{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|pp=9–10}} In the first book<!--????--> of this section<!--????--> on the "[[Schema (Kant)|schematism]]", Kant connects each of the purely logical categories of the understanding to the temporality of intuition to show that, although non-empirical, they do have purchase upon the objects of experience. The second book continues this line of argument in four chapters, each associated with one of the category groupings. In some cases, it adds a connection to the spatial dimension of intuition to the categories it analyzes.{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|pp=10–11}} The fourth chapter of this section, "The Analogies of Experience", marks a shift from "mathematical" to "dynamical" principles, that is, to those that deal with relations among objects. Some commentators consider this the most significant section of the ''Critique''.{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|p=11}} The analogies are three in number:
{{Link FA|pt}}
 
{{Link FA|vi}}
# ''Principle of persistence of substance'': Kant is here concerned with the general conditions of determining time-relations among the objects of experience. He argues that the unity of time implies that "all change must consist in the alteration of states in an underlying substance, whose existence and quantity must be unchangeable or conserved."<ref>see Kant, ''CPuR'' A182–26/B224–36</ref>
# ''Principle of temporal succession according to the law of causality'': Here Kant argues that "we can make determinate judgments about the objective succession of events, as contrasted to merely subjective successions of representations, only if every objective alteration follows a necessary rule of succession, or a causal law." This is Kant's most direct rejoinder to [[Humeanism#Causality and necessity|Hume's skepticism about causality]].<ref>see Kant, ''CPuR'' A186–211/B232–56</ref>
# ''Principle of simultaneity according to the law of reciprocity or community'': The final analogy argues that "determinate judgments that objects (or states of substance) in different regions of space exists simultaneously are possible only if such objects stand in mutual causal relation of community or reciprocal interaction." This is Kant's rejoinder to [[Leibniz]]'s thesis in the ''[[Monadology]]''.<ref>see Kant, ''CPuR'' A211-15/B256-62</ref>{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|pp=11–12}}
 
The fourth section of this chapter, which is not an analogy, deals with the empirical use of the modal categories. That was the end of the chapter in the A edition of the ''Critique''. The B edition includes one more short section, "The Refutation of Idealism". In this section, by analysis of the concept of self-consciousness, Kant argues that his transcendental idealism is a "critical" or "formal" idealism that does not deny the existence of reality apart from our subjective representations.{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|p=12}} The final chapter of "The Analytic of Principles" distinguishes ''[[phenomena]]'', of which we can have genuine knowledge, from ''[[noumena]]'', a term which refers to objects of pure thought that we cannot know, but to which we may still refer "in a negative sense".{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|pp=12–13}} An Appendix to the section further develops Kant's criticism of Leibnizian-Wolffian rationalism by arguing that its "dogmatic" metaphysics confuses the "mere features of concepts through which we think things ... [with] features of the objects themselves". Against this, Kant reasserts his own insistence upon the necessity of a sensible component in all genuine knowledge.{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|p=13}}
 
===Critique of metaphysics===
The second of the two Divisions of "The Transcendental Logic", "The Transcendental Dialectic", contains the "negative" portion of Kant's ''Critique'', which builds upon the "positive" arguments of the preceding "Transcendental Analytic" to expose the limits of metaphysical speculation. In particular, it is concerned to demonstrate as spurious the efforts of reason to arrive at knowledge independent of sensibility. This endeavor, Kant argues, is doomed to failure, which he claims to demonstrate by showing that reason, unbounded by sense, is always capable of generating opposing or otherwise incompatible conclusions. Like "the light dove, in free flight cutting through the air, the resistance of which it feels", reason "could get the idea that it could do even better in airless space".<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' A5/B8</ref> Against this, Kant claims that, absent epistemic friction, there can be no knowledge. Nevertheless, Kant's critique is not entirely destructive. He presents the speculative excesses of traditional metaphysics as inherent in our very capacity of reason. Moreover, he argues that its products are not without some (carefully qualified) ''regulative'' value.<ref>{{cite book |last=Guyer |first=Paul |title=Kant and the Claims of Knowledge |year=1987 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0521317245 |pages=52–55}}</ref>
 
====On the concepts of pure reason====
Kant calls the basic concepts of metaphysics "ideas". They are different from the concepts of understanding in that they are not limited by the critical stricture limiting knowledge to the conditions of possible experience and its objects. "Transcendental illusion" is Kant's term for the tendency of reason to produce such ideas.{{sfn|Jankowiak|2023|loc= §2(g)}} Although reason has a "logical use" of simply drawing inferences from principles, in "The Transcendental Dialectic", Kant is concerned with its purportedly "real use" to arrive at conclusions by way of unchecked regressive syllogistic ratiocination.{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|p=15}} The three categories of ''relation'', pursued without regard to the limits of possible experience, yield the three central ideas of traditional metaphysics:
 
# ''The soul'': the concept of substance as the ultimate subject;
# ''The world in its entirety'': the concept of causation as a completed series; and
# ''God'': the concept of community as the common ground of all possibilities.{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|p=15}}
 
Although Kant denies that these ideas can be objects of genuine cognition, he argues that they are the result of reason's inherent drive to unify cognition into a systematic whole.{{sfn|Jankowiak|2023|loc= §2(g)}} Leibnizian-Wolffian metaphysics was divided into four parts: ontology, psychology, cosmology, and theology. Kant replaces the first with the positive results of the first part of the ''Critique''. He proposes to replace the following three with his later doctrines of anthropology, the metaphysical foundations of natural science, and the critical postulation of human freedom and morality.{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|p=14}}
 
====Dialectical inferences of pure reason====
In the second of the two Books of "The Transcendental Dialectic", Kant undertakes to demonstrate the contradictory nature of unbounded reason. He does this by developing contradictions in each of the three metaphysical disciplines that he contends are in fact pseudosciences. This section of the ''Critique'' is long and Kant's arguments are extremely detailed. In this context, it not possible to do much more than enumerate the topics of discussion. The first chapter addresses what Kant terms the ''paralogisms''{{mdash}}i.e., false inferences{{mdash}}that pure reason makes in the metaphysical discipline of rational psychology. He argues that one cannot take the mere thought of "I" in the proposition "I think" as the proper cognition of "I" as an object. In this way, he claims to debunk various metaphysical theses about the substantiality, unity, and self-identity of the soul.{{sfn|Jankowiak|2023|loc=§2(g.i)}} The second chapter, which is the longest, takes up the topic Kant calls the [[Kant's antinomies|''antinomies of pure reason'']]{{mdash}}that is, the contradictions of reason with itself{{mdash}}in the metaphysical discipline of rational cosmology. Originally, Kant had thought that all transcendental illusion could be analyzed in [[Antinomy|antinomic terms]].{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|p=16}} He presents four cases in which he claims reason is able to prove opposing theses with equal plausibility:
 
# That "reason seems to be able to prove that the universe is both finite and infinite in space and time";
# that "reason seems to be able to prove that matter both is and is not infinitely divisible into ever smaller parts";
# that "reason seems to be able to prove that free will cannot be a causally efficacious part of the world (because all of nature is deterministic) and yet that it must be such a cause"; and,
# that "reason seems to be able to prove that there is and there is not a necessary being (which some would identify with God)".{{sfn|Jankowiak|2023|loc= §2(g.ii)}}{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|pp=16–17}}
 
Kant further argues in each case that his doctrine of transcendental idealism is able to resolve the antinomy.{{sfn|Jankowiak|2023|loc= §2(g.ii)}} The third chapter examines fallacious arguments about God in rational theology under the heading of the "Ideal of Pure Reason". (Whereas an ''idea'' is a pure concept generated by reason, an ''ideal'' is the concept of an idea as an ''individual thing''.{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|p=17}}) Here Kant addresses and claims to refute three traditional arguments for the existence of God: the [[ontological argument]], the [[cosmological argument]], and the [[argument from design|physio-theological argument]] (i.e., the argument from design).{{sfn|Jankowiak|2023|loc=§2(g.iii)}} The results of the transcendental dialectic so far appear to be entirely negative. In an Appendix to this section, Kant rejects such a conclusion. The ideas of pure reason, he argues, have an important ''regulatory'' function in directing and organizing our theoretical and practical inquiry. Kant's later works elaborate upon this function at length and in detail.{{sfn|Guyer|Wood|1998|p=18}}
 
===Moral thought===
{{Main|Kantian ethics}}
Kant developed his ethics, or moral philosophy, in three works: ''[[Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals]]'' (1785), ''[[Critique of Practical Reason]]'' (1788), and ''[[Metaphysics of Morals]]'' (1797).
With regard to [[morality]], Kant argued that the source of the [[Goodness and value theory|good]] lies not in anything outside the [[human]] subject, either in [[nature]] or given by [[God]], but rather is only the good will itself. A good will is one that acts from duty in accordance with the universal moral law that the autonomous human being freely gives itself. This law obliges one to treat humanity{{mdash}}understood as rational agency, and represented through oneself as well as others{{mdash}}as an [[end in itself]] rather than (merely) as [[means (philosophy)|means]] to other ends the individual might hold. Kant is known for his theory that all [[moral obligation]] is grounded in what he calls the "[[categorical imperative]]", which is derived from the concept of [[duty]]. He argues that the moral law is a principle of [[reason]] itself, not based on contingent facts about the world, such as what would make us happy; to act on the moral law has no other motive than "worthiness to be happy".<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' A806/B834</ref>
 
====Idea of freedom====
In the ''Critique of Pure Reason'', Kant distinguishes between the transcendental idea of freedom, which as a psychological concept is "mainly empirical" and refers to "whether a faculty of beginning a series of successive things or states from itself is to be assumed",<ref name="Kant, CPuR A448/B467">Kant, ''CPuR'' A448/B467</ref> and the practical concept of freedom as the independence of our will from the "coercion" or "necessitation through sensuous impulses". Kant finds it a source of difficulty that the practical idea of freedom is founded on the transcendental idea of freedom,<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' A533–34/B561–62</ref> but for the sake of practical interests uses the practical meaning, taking "no account of ... its transcendental meaning", which he feels was properly "disposed of" in the Third Antinomy, and as an element in the question of the freedom of the will is for philosophy "a real stumbling block" that has embarrassed speculative reason.<ref name="Kant, CPuR A448/B467"/>
 
Kant calls ''practical'' "everything that is possible through freedom"; he calls the pure practical laws that are never given through sensuous conditions, but are held analogously with the universal law of causality, moral laws. Reason can give us only the "pragmatic laws of free action through the senses", but pure practical laws given by reason ''a priori'' dictate "what is to be done".<ref name="Kant, CPuR A448/B467"/><ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' A800–02/B 828–30</ref> Kant's categories of freedom function primarily as conditions for the possibility for actions (i) to be free, (ii) to be understood as free, and (iii) to be morally evaluated. For Kant, although actions as theoretical objects are constituted by means of the theoretical categories, actions as practical objects (objects of practical use of reason, and which can be good or bad) are constituted by means of the categories of freedom. Only in this way can actions, as phenomena, be a consequence of freedom, and be understood and evaluated as such.<ref>[[Susanne Bobzien]], 'Die Kategorien der Freiheit bei Kant', in ''Kant: Analysen, Probleme, Kritik'' Vol. 1, 1988, 193–220.</ref>
 
====Categorical imperative====
Kant makes a distinction between categorical and [[hypothetical imperative]]s. A ''hypothetical'' imperative is one that must be obeyed to satisfy contingent desires. A ''categorical'' imperative binds [[rational agent]]s regardless of their desires: for example, all rational agents have a duty to respect other rational agents as individual ends in themselves, regardless of circumstances, even though it is sometimes in one's selfish interest to not do so. These imperatives are morally binding because of the categorical form of their maxims, rather than contingent facts about an agent.<ref>Driver 2007, p. 83.</ref> Unlike hypothetical imperatives, which bind us insofar as we are part of a group or society which we owe duties to, we cannot opt out of the categorical imperative, because we cannot opt out of being rational agents. We owe a duty to rationality by virtue of being rational agents; therefore, rational moral principles apply to all rational agents at all times.{{sfn|Johnson|2008}} Stated in other terms, with all forms of instrumental rationality excluded from morality, "the moral law itself, Kant holds, can only be the form of lawfulness itself, because nothing else is left once all content has been rejected".{{sfn|Schneewind|2010|p=261}}
 
Kant provides three formulations for the categorical imperative. He claims that these are necessarily equivalent, as all being expressions of the pure universality of the moral law as such;<ref>Kant, ''G''. 4:420–421, 436.</ref> many scholars are not convinced.<ref>Wood, Allen. (2017) ''Formulas of the Moral Law''. Cambridge University Press, pp. 74–78</ref> The formulas are as follows:
* ''Formula of Universal Law'':
** "Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you at the same time can will that it become a universal law";<ref name="Kant, G 4:421">Kant, ''G'' 4:421</ref> alternatively,
*** ''Formula of the Law of Nature'': "So act, as if the maxim of your action were to become through your will a universal law of nature."<ref name="Kant, G 4:421"/>
* ''Formula of Humanity as End in Itself'':
** "So act that you use humanity, as much in your own person as in the person of every other, always at the same time as an end and never merely as a means".<ref>Kant, ''G'' 4:429</ref>
* ''Formula of Autonomy'':
** "the idea of the will of every rational being as a will giving universal law",<ref>Kant, ''G'' 4:431; cf. 4:432</ref> or "Not to choose otherwise than so that the maxims of one's choice are at the same time comprehended with it in the same volition as universal law";<ref>Kant, ''G'' 4:440; cf. 4:432, 434, 438</ref> alternatively,
*** ''Formula of the Realm of Ends'': "Act in accordance with maxims of a universally legislative member for a merely possible realm of ends."<ref>Kant, ''G'' 4:439; cf. 4:433, 437–439</ref><ref>Wood, Allen. (2017) ''Formulas of the Moral Law''. Cambridge University Press, p.6</ref>
 
Kant defines ''maxim'' as a "subjective principle of volition", which is distinguished from an "objective principle or 'practical law.{{'"}} While "the latter is valid for every rational being and is a 'principle according to which they ought to act[,]' a maxim 'contains the practical rule which reason determines in accordance with the conditions of the subject (often their ignorance or inclinations) and is thus the principle according to which the subject does act.{{'"}}<ref>Caygill, Howard. (1995) ''A Kant Dictionary''. Blackwell Publishing, p. 289, citing ''GMM''.</ref>
 
Maxims fail to qualify as practical laws if they produce a contradiction in conception or a contradiction in the will when universalized. A contradiction in conception happens when, if a maxim were to be universalized, it ceases to make sense, because the "maxim would necessarily destroy itself as soon as it was made a universal law".<ref>Kant, ''G'' 4:403.</ref> For example, if the maxim 'It is permissible to break promises' was universalized, no one would trust any promises made, so the idea of a promise would become meaningless; the maxim would be [[Self-refuting idea|self-contradictory]] because, when it is universalized, promises cease to be meaningful. The maxim is not moral because it is logically impossible to universalize{{mdash}}that is, we could not conceive of a world where this maxim was universalized.<ref>Driver 2007, p. 88.</ref> A maxim can also be immoral if it creates a contradiction in the will when universalized. This does not mean a logical contradiction, but that universalizing the maxim leads to a state of affairs that no ''rational'' being would desire.
 
===="The Doctrine of Virtue"====
As Kant explains in the 1785 ''[[Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals]]'' and as its title directly indicates, that text is "nothing more than the search for and establishment of the ''supreme principle of morality''".<ref>Kant, ''GMM'' 4:392.</ref> His promised ''Metaphysics of Morals'' was much delayed and did not appear until its two parts, "The Doctrine of Right" and "The Doctrine of Virtue", were published separately in 1797 and 1798.<ref>Gregor, Mary J. (1996) "Translator's note on the text of The metaphysics of morals". In ''Practical Philosophy''. The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, p. 355.</ref> The first deals with political philosophy, the second with ethics. "The Doctrine of Virtue" provides "a very different account of ordinary moral reasoning" than the one suggested by the ''Groundwork''.{{sfn|Wood|2006|p=68}} It is concerned with ''duties of virtue'' or "ends that are at the same time duties".<ref>Kant, ''MM''. 6:382–391.</ref> It is here, in the ___domain of ethics, that the greatest innovation by ''The Metaphysics of Morals'' is to be found. According to Kant's account, "ordinary moral reasoning is fundamentally teleological{{mdash}}it is reasoning about what ends we are constrained by morality to pursue, and the priorities among these ends we are required to observe".{{sfn|Wood|2006|p=69}}
 
<blockquote>There are two sorts of ends that it is our duty to have: our own perfection and the happiness of others (''MS'' 6:385). "Perfection" includes both our natural perfection (the development of our talents, skills, and capacities of understanding) and moral perfection (our virtuous disposition) (''MS'' 6:387). A person's "happiness" is the greatest rational whole of the ends the person set for the sake of her<!--Kant, Wood????--> own satisfaction (''MS'' 6:387–388).{{sfn|Wood|2006|p=70}}</blockquote>
 
Kant's elaboration of this teleological doctrine offers up a moral theory very different from the one typically attributed to him on the basis of his foundational works alone.
 
===Political philosophy===
{{Main|Political philosophy of Immanuel Kant}}
{{Liberalism in Germany|People}}
{{republicanism sidebar}}
In ''Towards Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Project'', Kant listed several conditions that he thought necessary for ending wars and creating a lasting peace. They included a world of constitutional republics.<ref>Kant, ''PP'' 8:349–353</ref> His [[classical republican]] theory was extended in the ''Doctrine of Right'', the first part of the ''[[Metaphysics of Morals]]'' (1797).<ref>Manfred Riedel, ''Between Tradition and Revolution: The Hegelian Transformation of Political Philosophy'', Cambridge 1984</ref> Kant believed that [[Universal history (genre)|universal history]] leads to the ultimate world of republican states at peace, but his theory was not pragmatic. The process was described in ''Perpetual Peace'' as natural rather than rational:
{{blockquote|What affords this ''guarantee'' (surety) is nothing less than the great artist ''nature'' (''natura daedala rerum'') from whose mechanical course purposiveness shines forth visibly, letting concord arise by means of the discord between human beings even against their will; and for this reason nature, regarded as necessitation by a cause the laws of whose operation are unknown to us, is called ''fate'', but if we consider its purposiveness in the course of the world as the profound wisdom of a higher cause directed to the objective final end of the human race and predetermining this course of the world, it is called ''providence''.<ref>Kant, ''PP'' 8:360–362</ref>}}
 
Kant's political thought can be summarized as republican government and international organization: "In more characteristically Kantian terms, it is doctrine of the state based upon the law (''[[Rechtsstaat]]'') and of eternal peace. Indeed, in each of these formulations, both terms express the same idea: that of legal constitution or of 'peace through law.{{'"}}<ref>Hassner, Pierre. "Immanuel Kant", in ''History of Political Philosophy'', edited by Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, The University of Chicago Press, 1987, pp. 581–582</ref> "Kant's political philosophy, being essentially a legal doctrine, rejects by definition the opposition between moral education and the play of passions as alternate foundations for social life. The state is defined as the union of men under law. The state rightly so called is constituted by laws which are necessary a priori because they flow from the very concept of law. A regime can be judged by no other criteria nor be assigned any other functions, than those proper to the lawful order as such."<ref>Hassner, Pierre. "Immanuel Kant", in ''History of Political Philosophy'', edited by Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, The University of Chicago Press, 1987, p. 603</ref>
 
Kant opposed "democracy", which at his time meant [[direct democracy]], believing that majority rule posed a threat to individual liberty. He stated that "''democracy'' in the strict sense of the word is necessarily a ''despotism'' because it establishes an executive power in which all decide for and, if need be, against one (who thus does not agree), so that all, who are nevertheless not all, decide; and this is a contradiction of the general will with itself and with freedom."<ref>Kant, p. 8:352</ref>
 
As with most writers at the time, Kant distinguished three forms of government{{mdash}}namely, democracy, aristocracy, and monarchy{{mdash}}with [[mixed government]] as the most ideal form of it.<ref>Kant, ''PP'' 8:352</ref> He believed in [[republic]]an ideals and forms of governance, and [[rule of law]] brought on by them.<ref>Kant, pp. 8:349–8:353</ref> Although Kant published this as a "popular piece", [[Mary J. Gregor]] points out that two years later, in ''The Metaphysics of Morals'', Kant claims to demonstrate ''systematically'' that "establishing universal and lasting peace constitutes not merely a part of the doctrine of right, but rather the entire final end of the doctrine of right within the limits of mere reason".<ref>Kant, ''MM'' 6:355</ref><ref>Gregor, Mary J. "Introduction", in ''Practical Philosophy''. Cambridge University Press, p. 313</ref>
 
''The Doctrine of Right'', published in 1797, contains Kant's most mature and systematic contribution to political philosophy. It addresses duties according to law, which are "concerned only with protecting the external freedom of individuals" and indifferent to incentives. Although there is a moral duty "to limit ourselves to actions that are right, that duty is not part of [right] itself".{{sfn|Wood|2006|p=68}} Its basic political idea is that "each person's entitlement to be his or her own master is only consistent with the entitlements of others if public legal institutions are in place".<ref>Ripstein, Arthur. (2009) ''Force and Freedom: Kant's Legal and Political Philosophy''. Harvard University Press, p. 9.</ref> He formulates the universal principle of right as:
{{Blockquote|text=Any action is ''right'' if it can coexist with everyone's freedom in accordance with a universal law, or if on its maxim the freedom of choice of each can coexist with everyone's freedom in accordance with a universal law. (''MS'' 6:230).{{sfn|Wood|2006|p=68}}}}
 
===Religious writings===
{{Main|Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason}}
Starting in the 20th century, commentators tended to see Kant as having a strained relationship with religion, although in the nineteenth century this had not been the prevalent view. [[Karl Leonhard Reinhold]], whose letters helped make Kant famous, wrote: "I believe that I may infer without reservation that the interest of religion, and of Christianity in particular, accords completely with the result of the Critique of Reason."<ref>Karl Leonhard Reinhold, ''Letters on the Kantian Philosophy'' (1786), 3rd Letter</ref> According to [[Johann Friedrich Schultz]], who wrote one of the first commentaries on Kant: "And does not this system itself cohere most splendidly with the Christian religion? Do not the divinity and beneficence of the latter become all the more evident?"<ref>Johann Schultz, ''Exposition of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason'' (1784), 141.</ref> The reason for these views was Kant's moral theology and the widespread belief that his philosophy was the great antithesis to [[Spinozism]], which was widely seen as a form of sophisticated pantheism or even atheism. As Kant's philosophy disregarded the possibility of arguing for God through pure reason alone, for the same reasons it also disregarded the possibility of arguing against God through pure reason alone.
 
Kant directs his strongest criticisms of the organization and practices of religious organizations at those that encourage what he sees as a religion of counterfeit service to God.<ref>Kant, ''RBMR'' Part IV, First part, First section [6:157–163]</ref> Among the major targets of his criticism are external ritual, superstition, and a hierarchical church order. He sees these as efforts to make oneself pleasing to God in ways other than conscientious adherence to the principle of moral rightness in choosing and acting upon one's maxims. Kant's criticisms on these matters, along with his rejection of certain theoretical proofs for the existence of God that were grounded in pure reason (particularly the [[ontological argument]]) and his philosophical commentary on some Christian doctrines, have resulted in interpretations that see Kant as hostile to religion in general and to Christianity in particular.<ref>E.g., Walsh, W.H., 1967, "Kant, Immanuel: Philosophy of Religion", ''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', Volume Four, Paul Edwards (ed.), New York: Macmillan Publishing Co. Inc. & The Free Press, 322.</ref> Other interpreters, nevertheless, consider that Kant was trying to mark off defensible from indefensible Christian belief.<ref>{{cite encyclopedia|last1=Pasternack|first1=Lawrence|last2=Rossi|first2=Philip|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-religion/|title=Kant's Philosophy of Religion|encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|edition=Fall 2014|access-date=18 October 2019|archive-date=9 July 2010|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100709212423/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-religion/|url-status=live}}</ref>
 
Regarding Kant's conception of religion, some critics have argued that he was sympathetic to deism.<ref>For example Peter Byrne, who wrote about Kant's relationship with deism. Byrne, Peter (2007), ''Kant on God'', London: Ashgate, p. 159.</ref> Other critics have argued that Kant's moral conception moves from deism to theism (as moral theism), for example Allen W. Wood,<ref>Wood, Allen W. (1970), ''Kant's moral religion'', London and Ithaca: Cornell University Press, p. 16.</ref> as well as [[Merold Westphal]].<ref>Westphal, Merold (2010), ''The Emergence of Modern Philosophy of Religion'', in Taliaferro, Charles, Draper, Paul and Quinn, Philip (editors), ''A Companion to Philosophy of Religion'', Oxford: Blackwell, p. 135.</ref> As for Kant's book ''[[Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason|Religion within the Bounds of Mere Reason]]'', it was emphasized that Kant reduced religiosity to rationality, religion to morality, and Christianity to ethics;<ref>Iţu, Mircia (2004), ''Dumnezeu şi religia în concepţia lui Immanuel Kant din Religia în limitele raţiunii'', in Boboc, Alexandru and Mariş, N.I. (editors), ''Studii de istoria filosofiei universale'', volume 12, Bucharest: Romanian Academy.</ref> however, many interpreters, including Wood,<ref>Wood, Allen W. (2020), ''Kant and Religion'', Cambridge University Press, p. 2.</ref> alongside Lawrence Pasternack,<ref>See e.g., Lawrence Pasternack, ''Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Kant on Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason'' (New York, Routledge, 2014), pp. 239–240.</ref> now agree with [[Stephen Palmquist]]'s claim that a better way of reading Kant's ''Religion'' is to see him as raising morality to the status of religion.<ref>Palmquist, Stephen (1992), "Does Kant Reduce Religion to Morality?", ''Kant-Studien'' 83.2, pp. 129–148.</ref>
 
=== Aesthetics ===
{{See also | Kant's teleology}}
[[File:Immanuel Kant.jpg|thumb|Engraving of Kant by Friedrich Rosmäsler, 1822, from a painting by Todd Schorr]]
 
Kant discusses the subjective nature of aesthetic qualities and experiences in ''[[Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime]]'' (1764). Kant's contribution to [[aesthetics|aesthetic theory]] is developed in the ''[[Critique of Judgment|Critique of the Power of Judgment]]'' (1790), where he investigates the possibility and logical status of "judgments of taste". In the "Critique of Aesthetic Judgment", the first major division of the ''Critique of the Power of Judgment'', Kant used the term "aesthetic" in a manner that resembles its modern sense.<ref>Critique of Judgment in "Kant, Immanuel", ''[https://ia601704.us.archive.org/23/items/encyclopedia-of-philosophy_202010/Volume%205.pdf Encyclopedia of Philosophy]'', volume 5, Macmillan, 2006, accessed on 16 November 2024</ref> In the ''Critique of Pure Reason'', to note essential differences between judgments of taste, moral judgments, and scientific judgments, Kant abandoned the term "aesthetic" as "designating the critique of taste", noting that judgments of taste could never be "directed" by "laws ''a priori''".<ref>Kant, ''CPuR'' A22/B36</ref> After [[Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten]], who wrote ''Aesthetica'' (1750–58),{{efn|Beardsley, Monroe. "History of Aesthetics". ''Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. Vol. 1, section on "Toward a unified aesthetics", p. 25, Macmillan 1973. Baumgarten coined the term "aesthetics" and expanded, clarified, and unified Wolffian aesthetic theory, but had left the ''Aesthetica'' unfinished (See also: Tonelli, Giorgio. "Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten". ''Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. Vol. 1, Macmillan 1973). In Bernard's translation of the ''Critique of Judgment'' he indicates in the notes that Kant's reference in § 15 in regard to the identification of perfection and beauty is probably a reference to Baumgarten.}} Kant was one of the first philosophers to develop and integrate aesthetic theory into a unified and comprehensive philosophical system, utilizing ideas that played an integral role throughout his philosophy.<ref>German Idealism in "History of Aesthetics" ''Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. Vol 1. Macmillan, 1973.</ref> In the chapter "Analytic of the Beautiful" in the ''Critique of the Power of Judgment'', Kant states that beauty is not a property of an artwork or natural phenomenon, but is instead consciousness of the pleasure that attends the 'free play' of the imagination and the understanding. Even though it appears that we are using reason to decide what is beautiful, the judgment is not a cognitive judgment,{{efn|Kant's general discussions of the distinction between "cognition" and "conscious of" are also given in the ''Critique of Pure Reason'' (notably A320/B376), and section V and the conclusion of section VIII of his Introduction in ''Logic''.}} "and is consequently not logical, but aesthetical".<ref>Kant, ''CPJ'' §1</ref>
 
A pure judgement of taste is subjective since it refers to the emotional response of the subject and is based upon nothing but esteem for an object itself: it is a disinterested pleasure, and we feel that pure judgements of taste (i.e., judgements of beauty), lay claim to universal validity.<ref>Kant, ''CPJ'' §§ 20–22</ref> This universal validity is not derived from a determinate concept of beauty but from ''common sense''.<ref>Kant, ''CPJ'' §40</ref> Kant also believed that a judgment of taste shares characteristics with a moral judgment: both are disinterested, and we hold them to be universal.<ref>Kant, ''CPJ'' §59</ref><ref>{{cite book |last=Guyer |first=Paul |title=Kant and the Claims of Taste |year=1997 |publisher=Harvard University Press |isbn=978-0674500358 |pages=15–20}}</ref> In the chapter "Analytic of the Sublime," Kant identifies the [[Sublime (philosophy)|sublime]] as an aesthetic quality that, like beauty, is subjective, but unlike beauty, it refers to an indeterminate relationship between the faculties of the imagination and reason. It also shares the character of moral judgments in its engagement with reason.<ref>{{cite book |last=Clewis |first=Robert R. |title=The Kantian Sublime and the Revelation of Freedom |year=2009 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0521760867 |pages=48–52}}</ref> The feeling of the sublime, divided into two distinct modes (the mathematical and the dynamical sublime),<ref>Kant, ''CPJ'' §24</ref> describes two subjective moments that concern the relationship of the faculty of the imagination to reason. Some commentators argue that Kant's critical philosophy contains a third kind of the sublime, the moral sublime, which is the aesthetic response to the moral law or a representation, and a development of the "noble" sublime in Kant's theory of 1764.<ref>{{cite web |last=Clewis |first=Robert |year=2009 |title=The Kantian Sublime and the Revelation of Freedom |___location=Cambridge |publisher=Cambridge University Press |url=http://www.cambridge.org/us/knowledge/isbn/item2326741/?site_locale=en_US |access-date=8 December 2011 |archive-date=20 October 2012 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20121020224616/http://www.cambridge.org/us/knowledge/isbn/item2326741/?site_locale=en_US |url-status=live }}</ref>
 
The mathematical sublime results from the failure of the imagination to comprehend natural objects that appear boundless and formless, or appear "absolutely great".<ref>Kant, ''CPJ'' §§23–25</ref> This imaginative failure is then recuperated through the pleasure taken in reason's assertion of the concept of infinity. In this move the faculty of reason proves itself superior to our fallible sensible self.<ref>Kant, ''CPJ'' §§25–26</ref> In the dynamical sublime, there is the sense of annihilation of the sensible self as the imagination tries to comprehend a vast might. This power of nature threatens us but through the resistance of reason to such sensible annihilation, the subject feels a pleasure and a sense of the human moral vocation. This appreciation of moral feeling through exposure to the [[sublime (philosophy)|sublime]] helps to develop moral character.<ref>Kant, ''CPJ'' §§28–29</ref> Kant developed a theory of [[Humour|humor]],<ref>Kant, ''CPJ'' §54</ref> which has been interpreted as an "incongruity" theory. He illustrated his theory of humor by telling three narrative jokes in the ''Critique of Judgment''. He thought that the physiological impact of humor is akin to that of music.<ref>{{cite journal|last=Jakobidze-Gitman|first=Alexander|title=Kant's Situated Approach to Musicking and Joking|journal=Journal of Interdisciplinary Music Studies|year=2020|volume=10|pages=17–33|doi=10.25364/24.10:2020.2}}</ref>
 
Kant developed a distinction between an object of art as a material value subject to the conventions of society and the transcendental condition of the judgment of taste as a "refined" value in his ''Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Aim'' (1784). In the Fourth and Fifth Theses of that work he identified all art as the "fruits of unsociableness" due to men's "antagonism in society"<ref>Kant, ''UH'' 8:20–22</ref> and, in the Seventh Thesis, asserted that while such material property is indicative of a civilized state, only the ideal of morality and the universalization of refined value through the improvement of the mind "belongs to culture".<ref>Kant, ''UH'' 8:24–26.</ref>
 
===Anthropology===
Kant lectured on [[History of anthropology|anthropology]], the study of human nature, for twenty-three years.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Wilson |first1=Holly |title=Kant's Pragmatic Anthropology |url=https://archive.org/details/kantspragmatican00wils |url-access=limited |date=2006 |publisher=State University of New York Press |___location=Albany |isbn=978-0791468494 |page=[https://archive.org/details/kantspragmatican00wils/page/n21 7]}}</ref> His ''[[Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View]]'' was published in 1798. Transcripts of Kant's lectures on anthropology were published for the first time in 1997 in German.<ref>Thomas Sturm, ''Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen'' (Paderborn: Mentis Verlag, 2009).</ref> Kant was among the first people of his time to introduce anthropology as an intellectual area of study, long before the field gained popularity, and his texts are considered to have advanced the field. His point of view was to influence the works of later philosophers such as [[Martin Heidegger]] and [[Paul Ricœur]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Piercey |first1=Robert |last2=Philosophy Documentation Center |date=2011 |title=Kant and the Problem of Hermeneutics: Heidegger and Ricoeur on the Transcendental Schematism |url=http://www.pdcnet.org/oom/service?url_ver=Z39.88-2004&rft_val_fmt=&rft.imuse_id=idstudies_2011_0041_0003_0187_0202&svc_id=info:www.pdcnet.org/collection |journal=Idealistic Studies |volume=41 |issue=3 |pages=187–202 |doi=10.5840/idstudies201141315 |issn=0046-8541|url-access=subscription }}</ref>
 
Kant was the first to suggest using a dimensionality approach to human diversity. He analyzed the nature of the [[Hippocrates]]-[[Galen]] [[four temperaments]] and plotted in two dimensions "what belongs to a human being's faculty of desire":
"his natural aptitude or natural predisposition" and "his temperament or sensibility".<ref>Kant ''APPV'' 7:285</ref> Cholerics were described as emotional and energetic, phlegmatics as balanced and weak, sanguines as balanced and energetic, and melancholics as emotional and weak. These two dimensions reappeared in all subsequent models of temperament and personality traits. Kant viewed anthropology in two broad categories: (1) the physiological approach, which he referred to as "what nature makes of the human being"; and (2) the pragmatic approach, which explores the things that a human "can and should make of himself".<ref>Kant ''APPV'' 7:119</ref>
 
====Views on race====
Kant's theory of race and his prejudicial beliefs are among the most contentious areas of recent Kant scholarship.<ref name=":0">{{Cite book |title=Kant and the Concept of Race |publisher=State University of New York Press |year=2013 |isbn=978-1438443614 |editor-last=Mikkelsen |editor-first=Jon M. |___location=Albany, New York |pages=12–30 |language=English}}</ref><ref name=":1">{{Cite journal |last=Zorn |first=Daniel-Pascal |title=Kant{{mdash}}a Racist? |url=https://public-history-weekly.degruyter.com/?p=17156 |journal=Public History Weekly |year=2020 |volume=2020 |issue=8 |doi=10.1515/phw-2020-17156 |s2cid=225247836 |issn=2197-6376|url-access=subscription }}</ref>{{sfn|Kleingeld|2007|pp=573–592}}<!-- <ref>{{Cite journal |last=Kleingeld |first=Pauline |date=October 2007 |title=Kant's Second Thoughts on Race |url=https://philarchive.org/rec/KLEKST |journal=Philosophical Quarterly |volume=57 |issue=229 |pages=573–592 |doi=10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.498.x}}</ref>--> While few, if any, dispute the overt racism and chauvinism present in his work, a more contested question is the degree to which it degrades or invalidates his other contributions. His most severe critics assert that Kant intentionally manipulated science to support chattel slavery and discrimination.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Eze |first=Emmanuel |chapter=The Color of Reason: the Idea of 'Race' in Kant's Anthropology |date=1997 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/EZETCO |title=Postcolonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader |pages=103–140 |editor-last=Eze |editor-first=Emmanuel Chukwudi |publisher=Blackwell |access-date=20 April 2023}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Serequeberhan |first=T. |date=1996 |title=Eurocentrism in Philosophy: the Case of Immanuel Kant |journal=The Philosophical Forum |s2cid=170547963 |language=en}}</ref><ref name=":0" /> Others acknowledge that he lived in an era of immature science, with many erroneous beliefs, some racist, all appearing decades before evolution, molecular genetics, and other sciences that today are taken for granted.<ref name=":0" /><ref name=":1" /><ref>{{Cite web |title=The Philosophy Junkie: Immanuel Kant's Racism and Sexism with Professors Lucy Allais and Helga Varden on Apple Podcasts |url=https://podcasts.apple.com/us/podcast/immanuel-kants-racism-and-sexism-with-professors/id1512137924?i=1000496715962 |access-date=20 April 2023 |website=Apple Podcasts |language=en-US}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Geismann |first=Georg |date=1 January 2022 |title=Why Kant Was Not a 'Racist' |url=https://elibrary.duncker-humblot.com/article/69870/why-kant-was-not-a-racist |journal=Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik/Annual Review of Law and Ethics |volume=30 |issue=1 |pages=263–357 |doi=10.3790/jre.30.1.263 |s2cid=255676303 |issn=0944-4610|url-access=subscription }}</ref> Kant was one of the most notable Enlightenment thinkers to defend [[racism]]. The philosopher [[Charles W. Mills]] is unequivocal: "Kant is also seen as one of the central figures in the birth of modern 'scientific' racism. Whereas other contributors to early racial thought like Carolus Linnaeus and Johann Friedrich Blumenbach had offered only 'empirical' (scare-quotes necessary!) observation, Kant produced a full-blown ''theory'' of race."{{sfn|Mills|2017|pp=91–112|p=95}}
 
Using the [[four temperaments]] of ancient Greece, Kant proposed a hierarchy of racial categories including white Europeans, black Africans, and red Native Americans.<ref name=":2">{{Cite book |last=Kant |first=Immanuel |chapter=On the Different Races of Man |title=Race and the Enlightenment: a reader |publisher=Blackwell |year=1997 |isbn=063120136X |editor-last=Eze |editor-first=Emmanuel Chukwudi |___location=Cambridge, Mass. |pages=38–49 |oclc=34663347 |orig-date=1775, 1777}}</ref> Although he was a proponent of [[scientific racism]] for much of his career, Kant's views on race changed significantly in the last decade of his life, and he ultimately rejected racial hierarchies and European [[colonialism]] in ''[[Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch]]'' (1795).{{sfn|Kleingeld|2007|pp=573–592}}{{sfn|Mills|2017|pp=91–112}}<ref name=":2" />{{efn|Kant wrote that "[Whites] contain all the impulses of nature in affects and passions, all talents, all dispositions to culture and civilization and can as readily obey as govern. They are the only ones who always advance to perfection." He describes South Asians as "educated to the highest degree but only in the arts and not in the sciences". He goes on that Hindustanis can never reach the level of abstract concepts and that a "great hindustani man" is one who has "gone far in the art of deception and has much money". He states that the Hindus always stay the way they are and can never advance. About black Africans, Kant wrote that "they can be educated but only as servants, that is they allow themselves to be trained". To Kant, "the Negro can be disciplined and cultivated, but is never genuinely civilized. He falls of his own accord into savagery." Native Americans, Kant opined, "cannot be educated". He calls them unmotivated, lacking affect, passion and love, and describes them as too weak for labor, unfit for any culture, and too [[Four temperaments|phlegmatic]] for diligence. He said that Native Americans are "far below the Negro, who undoubtedly holds the lowest of all remaining levels by which we designate the different races". Kant stated that "Americans and Blacks cannot govern themselves. They thus serve only for slaves."{{sfn|Mills|2017|pp=169–193}}{{sfn|Bowersox|2016}}}} Kant was an opponent of [[miscegenation]], believing that whites would be "degraded" and that "fusing of races" is undesirable, for "not every race adopts the morals and customs of the Europeans". He states that "instead of assimilation, which was intended by the melting together of the various races, nature has here made a law of just the opposite".<ref>Kant ''APPV'' 7:320</ref> Kant was also an anti-Semite, believing that Jews were incapable of transcending material forces, which a moral order required. In this way, Jews are presented as the opposite of autonomous, rational Christians, and therefore incapable of being incorporated into an ethical Christian society. In his "Anthropology", Kant called the Jews "a nation of cheaters" and portrayed them as "a group that has followed not the path of transcendental freedom but that of enslavement to the material world".{{sfn|Shrage|2019}}
 
Mills wrote that Kant has been "sanitized for public consumption", his racist works conveniently ignored.{{sfn|Mills|2017|pp=95–97}} [[Robert Bernasconi]] stated that Kant "supplied the first scientific definition of race". [[Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze]] is credited with bringing Kant's contributions to racism to light in the 1990s among Western philosophers, who he believed often glossed over this part of his life and works.{{sfn|Bouie|2018}} Pauline Kleingeld argues that, while Kant "did defend a racial hierarchy until at least the end of the 1780s", his views on race changed significantly in works published in the last decade of his life. In particular, she argues that Kant rejected past views related to racial hierarchies and the diminished rights or moral status of non-whites in ''[[Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch|Perpetual Peace]]'' (1795). This work also saw him providing extended arguments against European [[colonialism]], which he claimed was morally unjust and incompatible with the equal rights held by indigenous populations. Kleingeld argues that this shift in Kant's views later in life has often been forgotten or ignored in the literature on Kant's racist anthropology, and that the shift suggests a belated recognition of the fact that racial hierarchy was incompatible with a universalized moral framework.{{sfn|Kleingeld|2007|pp=573–592}}
 
While Kant's racist rhetoric is indicative of the state of scholarship and science during the 18th century, German philosopher [[Daniel-Pascal Zorn]] explains the risk of taking period quotations out of context. Many of Kant's most outrageous quotations are from a series of articles from 1777–1788, a public exchange among Kant, Herder, the natural scientist [[Georg Forster]], and other scholars prominent in that period.<ref>{{Cite book |title=Kant and the Concept of Race: late eighteenth-century writings |date=2013 |others=Jon M. Mikkelsen |isbn=978-1461943129 |editor-last=Mikkelsen |editor-first=Jon M. |___location=Albany |oclc=861693001 |publisher=State University of New York Press}}</ref>{{sfn|Kuehn|2001|pp=298–301, 343–345}}<ref>cf. Kant, ''DCHR'' 8:91–106</ref> Kant asserts that all races of humankind are of the same species, challenging the position of Forster and others that the races were distinct species. While his commentary is clearly biased at times, certain extreme statements were patterned specifically to paraphrase or counter Forster and other authors.<ref name=":0" /><ref name=":1" /> By considering the full arc of Kant's scholarship, Zorn notes the progression in both his philosophical and his anthropological works, "with which he argues, against the ''zeitgeist'', for the unity of humanity".<ref name=":1" />
 
==Influence and legacy==
[[File:300Jahrfeier.jpg|thumb|Poster celebrating the 300 years of the [[University of Königsberg]], 1844. Among others, Kant and [[Johann Friedrich Herbart]] are honored.]]
Kant's influence on Western thought has been profound.{{efn|Oliver A. Johnson claims, "With the possible exception of Plato's ''Republic'', (''Critique of Pure Reason'') is the most important philosophical book ever written." Article on Kant within the collection ''Great thinkers of the Western World'', Ian P. McGreal, Ed., HarperCollins, 1992.}} Although the basic tenets of Kant's [[transcendental idealism]] (i.e., that space and time are ''a priori'' forms of human perception rather than real properties and the claim that formal logic and transcendental logic coincide) have been claimed to be falsified by modern science and logic,<ref>{{Cite book|last=Strawson|first=Peter|title=Bounds of Sense: Essay on Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason"|id={{ASIN|0415040302|country=uk}}}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web|title=Einstein on Kant|url=https://www.pitt.edu/~jdnorton/teaching/HPS_0410/chapters/significance_GR_geometry/Einstein_on_Kant.html#:~:text=Einstein%20wrote:,withstand%20the%20test%20of%20time.&text=However,%20if%20one%20does%20not,and%20norms%20of%20Kant%27s%20system.|access-date=2 September 2020|publisher=University of Pittsburgh|archive-date=9 August 2020|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200809030743/https://www.pitt.edu/~jdnorton/teaching/HPS_0410/chapters/significance_GR_geometry/Einstein_on_Kant.html#:~:text=Einstein%20wrote:,withstand%20the%20test%20of%20time.&text=However,%20if%20one%20does%20not,and%20norms%20of%20Kant%27s%20system.|url-status=live}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal|last=Perrick|first=Michael|date=1985|title=Kant and Kripke on Necessary Empirical Truths|journal=Mind|volume=94|issue=376|pages=596–598|doi=10.1093/mind/XCIV.376.596|jstor=2254731|issn=0026-4423}}</ref> and no longer set the intellectual agenda of contemporary philosophers, Kant is credited with having innovated the way philosophical inquiry has been carried on at least up to the early nineteenth century.<!--not very long! early twentieth?--> This shift consisted of several closely related innovations that, although highly contentious in themselves, have become important in subsequent philosophy and in the social sciences broadly construed:
* The human subject seen as the center of inquiry into human knowledge, such that it is impossible to philosophize about things as they exist independently of human perception or of how they are "for us";<ref>Stephen Palmquist, "The Architectonic Form of Kant's Copernican Logic", ''Metaphilosophy'' 17:4 (October 1986), pp. 266–288; revised and reprinted as Chapter III of [http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1 Kant's System of Perspectives] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120414204136/http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/ksp1 |date=14 April 2012 }}: An architectonic interpretation of the Critical philosophy (Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).</ref>
* the notion that is possible to discover and systematically explore the inherent limits of the human ability to know entirely ''a priori'';
* the notion of the "categorical imperative", an assertion that people are naturally endowed with the ability and obligation toward right reason and acting. Perhaps his most famous quote is drawn from the ''Critique of Practical Reason'': "Two things fill my mind with ever new and increasing admiration and reverence ... : ''the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me''";<ref>Kant, ''CPracR'' 5:161</ref>
* the concept of "conditions of possibility", as in his notion of "the conditions of possible experience"; that is, that things, knowledge, and forms of consciousness rest on prior conditions that make them possible, so that, to understand or to know them, several conditions must be understood:
:* the claim that objective experience is actively constituted or constructed by the functioning of the human mind;
:* the concept of moral autonomy as central to humanity; and
:* the assertion of the principle that human beings should be treated as ends rather than as mere means.
 
Kant's ideas have been incorporated into a variety of schools of thought. These include [[German idealism]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Beiser |first=Frederick C. |author-link=Frederick C. Beiser |title=German Idealism: The Struggle Against Subjectivism, 1781–1801 |publisher=[[Harvard University Press]] |date=2002 |isbn=978-0674007703 |pages=Part I}}</ref> [[Marxism]],<ref>{{cite book |last=McLellan |first=David |title=Marxism after Marx |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan |date=1998 |isbn=978-0333738399 |pages=22–25}}</ref> [[positivism]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Kolakowski |first=Leszek |title=Positivist Philosophy: From Hume to the Vienna Circle |publisher=Penguin Books |date=1972 |isbn=0140212248 |pages=67–69}}</ref> [[phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Carman |first=Taylor |title=Merleau-Ponty |publisher=Routledge |date=2008 |isbn=978-0415360616 |pages=34–36}}</ref> [[existentialism]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Kaufmann |first=Walter |title=Existentialism: From Dostoevsky to Sartre |publisher=Meridian Books |date=1989 |isbn=978-0452009301 |pages=9–12}}</ref> [[critical theory]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Habermas |first=Jürgen |title=The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures |publisher=MIT Press |date=1987 |isbn=978-0745608303 |pages=109–113}}</ref> [[linguistic philosophy]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Dummett |first=Michael |title=Origins of Analytical Philosophy |publisher=Harvard University Press |date=1996 |isbn=978-0674644731 |pages=45–47}}</ref> [[structuralism]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Piaget |first=Jean |title=Structuralism |publisher=Routledge |date=2001 |isbn=978-0415262491 |pages=10–12}}</ref> [[post-structuralism]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Norris |first=Christopher |title=Deconstruction: Theory and Practice |publisher=Routledge |date=2003 |isbn=978-0415061742 |pages=40–42}}</ref> and [[deconstruction]].<ref>{{cite book |last=Culler |first=Jonathan |title=On Deconstruction: Theory and Criticism after Structuralism |publisher=Cornell University Press |date=2007 |isbn=978-0801479182 |pages=53–56}}</ref>
 
===Historical influence===
 
[[File:Kant Kaliningrad.jpg|thumb|upright=.8|Statue of Kant in [[Kaliningrad]], Russia. Replica by {{Interlanguage link|Harald Haacke|de}} of the original by [[Christian Daniel Rauch]] was lost in 1945.]]
 
During his own life, much critical attention was paid to Kant's thought. He influenced [[Karl Leonhard Reinhold|Reinhold]], [[Johann Gottlieb Fichte|Fichte]], [[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Schelling|Schelling]], [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]], and [[Novalis]] during the 1780s and 1790s. [[Samuel Taylor Coleridge]] was greatly influenced by Kant and helped to spread awareness of him, and of German Idealism generally, in the UK and the US. In his ''[[Biographia Literaria]]'' (1817), he credits Kant's ideas in coming to believe that the mind is not a passive, but an active agent in the apprehension of reality. Hegel was one of Kant's first major critics. In Hegel's view the entire project of setting a "transcendental subject" (i.e., human consciousness) apart from the living individual as well as from nature, history, and society was fundamentally flawed,<ref>{{Cite book|last=Hegel|first=Georg Wilhelm Friedrich|title=Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline|year=1827|___location=Heidelberg|pages=14–15}}</ref> although parts of that very project could be put to good use in a new direction. Similar concerns motivated Hegel's criticisms of Kant's concept of moral autonomy, to which Hegel opposed an ethic focused on the "ethical life" of the community.{{efn|Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, ''Natural Law: The Scientific Ways of Treating Natural Law, Its Place in Moral Philosophy, and Its Relation to the Positive Sciences''. trans. T.M. Knox. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1975. Hegel's mature view and his concept of "ethical life" is elaborated in his ''Philosophy of Right''. Hegel, ''Philosophy of Right''. trans. T.M. Knox. Oxford University Press, 1967.}} In a sense, Hegel's notion of "ethical life" is meant to subsume, rather than replace, [[Kantian ethics]]. And Hegel can be seen as trying to defend Kant's idea of freedom as going beyond finite "desires", by means of reason. Thus, in contrast to later critics like Nietzsche or Russell, Hegel shares some of Kant's concerns.{{efn|Robert Pippin's ''Hegel's Idealism'' (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989) emphasizes the continuity of Hegel's concerns with Kant's. Robert Wallace, ''Hegel's Philosophy of Reality, Freedom, and God'' (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005) explains how Hegel's ''Science of Logic'' defends Kant's idea of freedom as going beyond finite "inclinations", contra skeptics such as David Hume.}}
 
Kant's thinking on religion was used in Britain by philosophers such as [[Thomas Carlyle]]<ref>{{Cite web |last=Cody |first=David |date= |title=Carlyle: Sources and Influence |url=https://victorianweb.org/authors/carlyle/sources.html |access-date=28 July 2023 |website=The Victorian Web}}</ref> to challenge the nineteenth-century decline in religious faith. British Catholic writers, notably [[G. K. Chesterton]] and [[Hilaire Belloc]], followed this approach.<ref>{{cite book |last=Morse |first=David |title=The Age of Virtue: British Culture from the Restoration to Romanticism |year=2000 |publisher=Macmillan |isbn=978-0333913918 |pages=198–200}}</ref> Criticisms of Kant were common in the realist views of the new [[positivism]] at that time. [[Arthur Schopenhauer]] was strongly influenced by Kant's [[transcendental idealism]]. Like [[Gottlob Ernst Schulze]], [[Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi]], and Fichte before him, Schopenhauer was critical of Kant's theory of the thing-in-itself. Things-in-themselves, they argued, are neither the cause of what we observe, nor are they completely beyond our access. Ever since the ''Critique of Pure Reason'', philosophers have been critical of Kant's theory of the thing-in-itself. Many have argued that, if such a thing exists beyond experience, then one cannot posit that it affects us causally, since that would entail stretching the category "causality" beyond the realm of experience.{{efn|For a review of this problem and the relevant literature see ''The Thing in Itself and the Problem of Affection'' in the revised edition of Henry Allison's ''Kant's Transcendental Idealism''.}}
 
With the success and wide influence of Hegel's writings, Kant's own influence began to wane, but a re-examination of his ideas began in Germany in 1865 with the publication of ''Kant und die Epigonen'' by [[Otto Liebmann]], whose motto was "Back to Kant". There proceeded an important revival of Kant's theoretical philosophy, known as [[Neo-Kantianism]]. Kant's notion of "critique" has been more broadly influential. The early German Romantics, especially [[Friedrich Schlegel]] in his "Athenaeum Fragments", used Kant's reflexive conception of criticism in their Romantic theory of poetry.<ref>Schlegel, Friedrich. "Athenaeum Fragments", in ''Philosophical Fragments''. Trans. Peter Firchow. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1991. See especially fragments Nos. 1, 43, 44.</ref> Also in aesthetics, [[Clement Greenberg]], in his classic essay "Modernist Painting", uses Kantian criticism, what Greenberg refers to as "immanent criticism", to justify the aims of [[Abstract art|abstract painting]], a movement Greenberg saw as aware of the key limitation—flatness—that makes up the medium of painting.<ref>Greenberg, Clement. "Modernist Painting", in ''The Philosophy of Art'', ed. Alex Neill and Aaron Ridley, McGraw-Hill, 1995.</ref> The French philosopher [[Michel Foucault]] was also greatly influenced by Kant's notion of "critique" and wrote several pieces on Kant for a re-thinking of the Enlightenment as a form of "critical thought". He went so far as to classify his own philosophy as a "critical history of modernity, rooted in Kant".<ref>See "Essential Works of Foucault: 1954–1984 vol. 2: Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology". Ed. by James Faubion, Trans. Robert Hurley et al. New York City: The New Press, 1998 (2010 reprint). See "Foucault, Michel, 1926 –" entry by Maurice Florence.</ref>
 
Kant believed that mathematical truths were forms of [[Synthetic a priori|synthetic ''a priori'']] knowledge, which means they are necessary and universal, yet known through the ''a priori'' intuition of space and time, as transcendental preconditions of experience.<ref>For a discussion and qualified defense of this position, see Stephen Palmquist, "A Priori Knowledge in Perspective: (I) Mathematics, Method and Pure Intuition", ''The Review of Metaphysics'' 41:1 (September 1987), pp. 3–22.</ref> Kant's often brief remarks about [[mathematics]] influenced the mathematical school known as [[intuitionism]], a movement in [[philosophy of mathematics]] opposed to [[David Hilbert]]'s [[Formalism (mathematics)|formalism]], and [[Gottlob Frege]] and [[Bertrand Russell]]'s [[logicism]].{{efn|[[Stephan Körner|Körner, Stephan]], ''The Philosophy of Mathematics'', Dover, 1986. For an analysis of Kant's writings on mathematics see, Friedman, Michael, ''Kant and the Exact Sciences'', Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1992.}}
 
===Influence on modern thinkers===
[[File:DBP - 250 Jahre Immanuel Kant - 90 Pfennig - 1974.jpg|thumb|upright|[[West German]] postage stamp, 1974, commemorating the 250th anniversary of Kant's birth]]
 
With his ''Perpetual Peace'', Kant is considered to have foreshadowed many of the ideas that have come to form the [[democratic peace theory]], one of the main controversies in [[political science]].<ref>{{cite journal|last=Ray|first=James Lee |url=http://www.mtholyoke.edu/acad/intrel/ray.htm |title=Does Democracy Cause Peace?|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080217032515/http://www.mtholyoke.edu/acad/intrel/ray.htm |archive-date=17 February 2008|journal=Annual Review of Political Science|year=1998|volume=1|pages=27–46|doi=10.1146/annurev.polisci.1.1.27|doi-access=|url-access=subscription}}</ref> More concretely, constructivist theorist Alexander Wendt proposed that the anarchy of the international system could evolve from the "brutish" Hobbesian anarchy understood by realist theorists, through Lockean anarchy, and ultimately a Kantian anarchy in which states would see their self-interests as inextricably linked to the well being of other states, thus transforming international politics into a far more peaceful form.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Wendt |first=Alexander |title=Social Theory of International Politics |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=1999 |pages=chapter 6}}</ref>
 
Prominent recent Kantians include the British philosophers [[P. F. Strawson]],{{efn|Strawson, P.F., ''The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason''. Routledge: 2004. When first published in 1966, this book forced many Anglo-American philosophers to reconsider Kant's ''Critique of Pure Reason''.}} [[Onora O'Neill]],<ref>{{Cite news|url=https://www.nytimes.com/2017/03/14/books/onora-oneill-wins-holberg-prize.html|title=Onora O'Neill Wins Holberg Prize for Academic Research|last=Aridi|first=Sara|date=14 March 2017|work=The New York Times|access-date=9 January 2019|archive-date=9 January 2019|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190109111404/https://www.nytimes.com/2017/03/14/books/onora-oneill-wins-holberg-prize.html|url-status=live}}</ref> and [[Quassim Cassam]],<ref>Cassam, Q. ''The Possibility of Knowledge'' Oxford: 2009</ref> and the American philosophers [[Wilfrid Sellars]],<ref>Sellars, Wilfrid, ''Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes''. Ridgeview Publishing Company, 1967</ref> [[Lewis White Beck]]<ref>[https://books.google.com/books?id=Ijpj1tB3Qr0C&q=lEWIS+wHITE+bECK#v=snippet&q=lEWIS%20wHITE%20bECK&f=false ''Dictionary of Modern American Philosphers''. Shook, John R. Ed. Thoemmes Continuum, Bristol], 2005 p. 166 {{ISBN|9781843710370}} Lewis White Beck on Google Books</ref><ref>[https://www.researchgate.net/publication/236806211_Lewis_White_Beck_on_Reasons_and_Causes "Lewis White Beck On Reasons and Causes", Guyer, Paul. ''Journal on the History of Ideas'' July, 2002 63 (3) pp. 539–548 Lewis White Beck on researchgate.net]</ref> and [[Christine Korsgaard]].{{efn|Korsgaard, Christine. ''Creating the Kingdom of Ends''. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996.{{ISBN|978-0521496445}} ''Not a commentary, but a defense of a broadly Kantian approach to ethics''.}} Due to the influence of Strawson and Sellars, among others, there has been a renewed interest in Kant's view of the mind. Central to many debates in [[philosophy of psychology]] and [[cognitive science]] is Kant's conception of the unity of consciousness.{{efn|[[Andrew Brook|Brook, Andrew]]. ''Kant and the Mind''. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. See also, Meerbote, R. "Kant's [[Functionalism (philosophy of mind)|Functionalism]]". In: J.C. Smith, ed. ''Historical Foundations of Cognitive Science''. Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel, 1991. Brook has an article on Kant's View of the Mind in the [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-mind/ Stanford Encyclopedia] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100709014732/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-mind/ |date=9 July 2010 }}}}
 
[[Jürgen Habermas]] and [[John Rawls]] are two significant political and moral philosophers whose work is strongly influenced by Kant's moral philosophy.{{efn|See Habermas, J. ''Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action''. Trans. Christian Lenhardt and Shierry Weber Nicholsen. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1996. For Rawls see, Rawls, John. ''Theory of Justice'' Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1971. Rawls has a well-known essay on Kant's concept of good. See, Rawls, "Themes in Kant's Moral Philosophy" in ''Kant's Transcendental Deductions''. Ed. Eckart Förster. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1989.}} They have argued against relativism,<ref>Habermas, J. (1994): The Unity of Reason in the Diversity of Its Voices. In: Habermas, J. (Ed.): ''Postmetaphysical Thinking. Political Essays'', Cambridge, Massachusetts: 115–148.</ref> supporting the Kantian view that universality is essential to any viable moral philosophy. [[Mou Zongsan]]'s study of Kant has been cited as a highly crucial part in the development of Mou's personal philosophy, namely [[New Confucianism]]. Widely regarded as the most influential Kant scholar in China, Mou's rigorous critique of Kant's philosophy{{mdash}}having translated all three of Kant's [[Critique of Pure Reason|critiques]]{{mdash}}served as an ardent attempt to reconcile Chinese and Western philosophy whilst increasing pressure to [[Westernize]] in China.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Palmquist |first1=Stephen |title=Cultivating Personhood: Kant and Asian Philosophy |url=https://archive.org/details/cultivatingperso00palm |url-access=limited |year= 2010 |publisher=De Gruyter, Inc. |___location=Hong Kong |isbn=978-3110226249|page=[https://archive.org/details/cultivatingperso00palm/page/n43 25] |edition=}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Wing-Cheuk |first1=Chan |title=Mou Zongsan's Transformation of Kant's Philosophy |journal=Journal of Chinese Philosophy |date=21 February 2006 |volume=33 |issue=1 |page=1 |doi=10.1111/j.1540-6253.2006.00340.x }}</ref>
 
[[File:Kant-Münze DDR.jpg|thumb|upright|[[East German]] commemorative coin honoring Kant, 1974]]
 
Because of the thoroughness of Kant's paradigm shift, his influence extends well beyond this to thinkers who neither specifically refer to his work nor use his terminology. Kant's influence extended to the social, behavioral, and physical sciences{{mdash}}as in the sociology of [[Max Weber]], the psychology of [[Jean Piaget]], and [[Carl Jung]].<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Balanovskiy |first1=Valentin |title=Whether jung was a kantian? |journal=Con-Textos Kantianos |year=2016 |issue=4 |pages=118–126 |doi=10.5281/zenodo.2550828 |url=https://www.researchgate.net/publication/323218719 |access-date=29 May 2020 |archive-date=20 December 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20201220055819/https://www.researchgate.net/publication/323218719_Whether_jung_was_a_kantian |url-status=live }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Balanovskiy |first1=Valentin |title=Kant and Jung on the prospects of Scientific Psychology |journal=Estudos Kantianos |year=2017 |volume=5 |issue=1 |pages=357–390 |doi=10.36311/2318-0501.2017.v5n1.26.p375 |url=https://philpapers.org/archive/BALIKA.pdf |doi-access=free |access-date=29 May 2020 |archive-date= |archive-url= |url-status= }}</ref> Kant's work on mathematics and synthetic ''a priori'' knowledge is also cited by the theoretical physicist [[Albert Einstein]] as an early influence on his intellectual development, although it was one which he later criticized and rejected.<ref>Isaacson, Walter. "Einstein: His Life and Universe". p. 20.</ref> In the 2020s, there was a renewed interest in Kant's theory of mind from the point of view of [[formal logic]] and [[computer science]].<ref>Theodora Achourioti & Michiel van Lambalgen, 'A Formalization of Kant's Transcendental Logic', ''The Review of Symbolic Logic'', 4 (2011), 254–289.</ref>
 
==Bibliography==
Unless otherwise noted, all citations are to ''The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant in English Translation'', 16 vols., ed. Guyer, Paul, and Wood, Allen W. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992. Citations in the article are to individual works per abbreviations in ''List of major works'' below.
* ''Theoretical Philosophy, 1755–1770''. Ed. and trans. David Walford with Ralf Meerbote. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
* ''Lectures on Logic''. Ed. and trans. J. Michael Young. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
* ''Opus postumum''. Ed. Eckart Förster, trans. Eckart Förster and Michael Rosen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993
* ''Practical Philosophy''. Ed. and trans. Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
* ''Religion and Rational Theology''. Ed. and trans. [[Allen W. Wood]] and [[George di Giovanni]]. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996
* ''Lectures on Metaphysics''. Ed. and trans. Karl Ameriks and Steve Naragon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
* ''Lectures on Ethics''. Ed. Peter Heath and J.B. Schneewind, trans. Peter Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
* ''Critique of Pure Reason''. Ed. and trans. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
* ''Correspondence''. Ed. and trans. Arnulf Zweig. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
* ''Critique of the Power of Judgment''. Ed. Paul Guyer, trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
* ''Theoretical Philosophy after 1781''. Ed. Henry Allison and Peter Heath, trans. Gary Hatfield, Michael Friedman, Henry Allison, and Peter Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.
* ''Notes and Fragments''. Ed. Paul Guyer, trans. Curtis Bowman, Paul Guyer, and Frederick Rauscher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005.
* ''Anthropology, History, and Education'', Ed. Günter Zöller and Robert B. Louden. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.
* ''Lectures on Anthropology'', Ed. Allen W. Wood and Robert B. Louden Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012.
* ''Natural Science'', Ed. Eric Watkins. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012.
 
===List of major works===
Abbreviations used in body of article are boldface in brackets. Unless otherwise noted, pagination is to the critical ''Akademie'' edition, which can be found in the margins of the Cambridge translations.
* 1749: ''[[Thoughts on the True Estimation of Living Forces]]'' (''Gedanken von der wahren Schätzung der lebendigen Kräfte'')
* 1755: ''[[Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens]]'' ['''UNH'''] ({{lang|de|Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und Theorie des Himmels}})
* 1755: ''Brief Outline of Certain Meditations on Fire'' (''Meditationum quarundam de igne succinta delineatio'' ([[master's thesis]] under [[Johann Gottfried Teske]]))<ref>The thesis was submitted on 17 April 1755. "The public examination was held four weeks later on 13 May, and the degree was formally awarded on 12 June" (Eric Watkins, ''Kant: Natural Science'', Cambridge University Press, 2012, p. 309).</ref><ref>Eric Watkins (ed.), ''Kant and the Sciences'', Oxford University Press, 2001, p. 27.</ref><ref>Martin Schonfeld, ''The Philosophy of the Young Kant: The Precritical Project'', Oxford University Press, 2000, p. 74.</ref><ref>Available [https://korpora.zim.uni-duisburg-essen.de/kant/aa01/369.html online at Bonner Kant-Korpus] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160306131152/https://korpora.zim.uni-duisburg-essen.de/kant/aa01/369.html |date=6 March 2016 }}.</ref>
* 1755: ''A New Elucidation of the First Principles of Metaphysical Cognition'' (''Principiorum primorum cognitionis metaphysicae nova dilucidatio'' ([[doctoral thesis]]))<ref>The thesis was publicly disputed on 27 September 1755 (Kuehn 2001, p. 100).</ref>{{efn|available [https://korpora.zim.uni-duisburg-essen.de/kant/aa01/385.html online at Bonner Kant-Korpus] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160306131856/https://korpora.zim.uni-duisburg-essen.de/kant/aa01/385.html |date=6 March 2016 }}.}}
* 1756: ''The Use in Natural Philosophy of Metaphysics Combined with Geometry, Part I: Physical Monadology'' ['''PM'''] (''Metaphysicae cum geometrica iunctae usus in philosophia naturali, cuius specimen I. continet monadologiam physicam'', abbreviated as ''Monadologia Physica'' (thesis as a prerequisite of associate professorship))<ref>Kant's application for the position was unsuccessful. He defended it on 10 April 1756 (Kuehn 2001, p. 102).</ref>
* 1762: ''[[The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures]]'' (''Die falsche Spitzfindigkeit der vier syllogistischen Figuren'')
* 1763: ''[[The Only Possible Argument in Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God]]'' (''Der einzig mögliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseins Gottes'')
* 1763: ''Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy'' ['''NQ'''] (''Versuch den Begriff der negativen Größen in die Weltweisheit einzuführen'')
* 1764: ''[[Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime]]'' ['''OFBS'''] (''Beobachtungen über das Gefühl des Schönen und Erhabenen'')
* 1764: ''Essay on the Illness of the Head'' (''Über die Krankheit des Kopfes'')
* 1764: ''Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality'' (the ''Prize Essay'') ['''PNTM'''] (''Untersuchungen über die Deutlichkeit der Grundsätze der natürlichen Theologie und der Moral'')
* 1766: ''Dreams of a Spirit-Seer'' ['''DSS'''] (''Träume eines Geistersehers'')<ref>Available [https://archive.org/details/dreamsofspiritse00kant online at Archive.org].</ref>
* 1768: ''On the Ultimate Ground of the Differentiation of Regions in Space'' [1768] (''Von dem ersten Grunde des Unterschiedes der Gegenden im Raume'')<ref>Immanuel Kant, [https://philpapers.org/rec/KANCTU "Concerning the ultimate ground of the differentiation of directions in space"] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180716082315/https://philpapers.org/rec/KANCTU |date=16 July 2018 }}.</ref>
* 1770: ''Dissertation on the Form and Principles of the Sensible and the Intelligible World'' ['''ID'''] (''De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis forma et principiis'' [doctoral thesis])<ref>The thesis was publicly disputed on 21 August 1770 (Kuehn 2001, p. 189).</ref><ref>Available [https://books.google.com/books?id=dNRKAQAAMAAJ&pg=PA123 online at Google Books] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200803105335/https://books.google.com/books?id=dNRKAQAAMAAJ&pg=PA123 |date=3 August 2020 }}.</ref><ref>English translation available [[:s:Kant's Inaugural Dissertation of 1770|online at Wikisource]].</ref>
* 1775: ''On the Different Races of Man'' (''Über die verschiedenen Rassen der Menschen'')
* 1781: First edition of the ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'' ['''CPuR A''']<ref>{{cite web|author=Immanuel Kant|url=http://etext.library.adelaide.edu.au/k/kant/immanuel/k16p/|title=The Critique of Pure Reason|publisher=Etext.library.adelaide.edu.au|access-date=24 July 2009|url-status=dead|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20081202072513/http://etext.library.adelaide.edu.au/k/kant/immanuel/k16p/|archive-date=2 December 2008}}</ref> (''Kritik der reinen Vernunft'')<ref>{{cite web|author=Immanuel Kant|url=http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/krva/krva.htm|title=Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft – 1. Auflage – Kapitel 1|publisher=Projekt Gutenberg-DE|access-date=24 July 2009|language=de|archive-date=9 June 2007|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20070609150201/http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/krva/krva.htm|url-status=live}}</ref>
* 1783: ''[[Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics]]'' ['''PFM'''] (''Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik'')
* 1784: "[[What Is Enlightenment?|An Answer to the Question: What Is Enlightenment?]]" ['''WE?'''] ("''Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklärung?''")<ref>{{cite web|author=Frank-Christian Lilienweihs|url=http://www.prometheusonline.de/heureka/philosophie/klassiker/kant/aufklaerung.htm|title=Immanuel Kant: Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklaerung?|publisher=Prometheusonline.de|date=10 June 1999|access-date=24 July 2009|archive-date=1 August 2009|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090801001752/http://www.prometheusonline.de/heureka/philosophie/klassiker/kant/aufklaerung.htm|url-status=live}}</ref>
* 1784: "[[Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose]]" ['''UH'''] ("''Idee zu einer allgemeinen Geschichte in weltbürgerlicher Absicht''")
* 1785: "Determination of the Concept of a Human Race" ['''DCHR'''] (''Bestimmung des Begriffs einer Menschenrace'')
* 1785: ''[[Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals]]'' ['''G'''] (''Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten'')
* 1786: ''[[Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science]]'' ['''MFNS'''] (''Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft'')
* 1786: "[https://archive.org/details/KantOrientFerrerMarch2014 What does it mean to orient oneself in thinking?]" ['''OT''']("''Was heißt: sich im Denken orientieren?''")
* 1786: ''Conjectural Beginning of Human History'' ['''CB'''] (''Mutmaßlicher Anfang der Menschengeschichte'')
* 1787: Second edition of the ''[[Critique of Pure Reason]]'' ['''CPuR B''']<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/cpr/toc.html|title=Critique of Pure Reason|publisher=Hkbu.edu.hk|date=31 October 2003|access-date=24 July 2009|archive-date=27 April 2009|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090427130629/http://www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/cpr/toc.html|url-status=live}}</ref> (''Kritik der reinen Vernunft'')<ref>{{cite web|url=http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/krvb/krvb.htm|title=Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft – 2. Auflage – Kapitel 1|publisher=Projekt Gutenberg-DE|date=20 July 2009|access-date=24 July 2009|language=de|archive-date=26 December 2005|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20051226212924/http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/krvb/krvb.htm|url-status=live}}</ref>
* 1788: ''[[Critique of Practical Reason]]'' ['''CPracR'''] (''Kritik der praktischen Vernunft'')<ref>{{cite web|author=Immanuel Kant|url=http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/kritikpr/kritikpr.htm|title=Immanuel Kant: Kritik der praktischen Vernunft – Kapitel 1|publisher=Projekt Gutenberg-DE|access-date=24 July 2009|language=de|archive-date=9 June 2007|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20070609150443/http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/kritikpr/kritikpr.htm|url-status=live}}</ref>
* 1790: ''[[Critique of Judgment]]'' ['''CPJ'''] (''Kritik der Urteilskraft'')<ref>[[s:The Critique of Judgment]]</ref>
* 1793: ''[[Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason]]'' ['''RBMR'''] (''Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der bloßen Vernunft'')<ref name="KReligion"/><ref>{{cite web|author=Immanuel Kant|url=http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/ethics/kant/religion/religion-within-reason.htm|title=Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone by Immanuel Kant 1793|publisher=Marxists.org|access-date=24 July 2009|archive-date=1 June 2009|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090601192705/http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/ethics/kant/religion/religion-within-reason.htm|url-status=live}}</ref>
* 1793: ''On the Old Saw: That May be Right in Theory But It Won't Work in Practice'' ['''TP'''] ''(Über den Gemeinspruch: Das mag in der Theorie richtig sein, taugt aber nicht für die Praxis)''
* 1795: ''[[Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch]]''<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.mtholyoke.edu/acad/intrel/kant/kant1.htm|title=Immanuel Kant, "Perpetual Peace"|publisher=Mountr Holyoke |access-date=24 July 2009|archive-date=6 April 2019|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190406161945/https://www.mtholyoke.edu/acad/intrel/kant/kant1.htm|url-status=live}}</ref> ['''PP'''] ("''Zum ewigen Frieden''")<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.uni-kassel.de/fb5/frieden/themen/Theorie/kant.html|title=Immanuel Kant: Zum ewigen Frieden, 12.02.2004 (Friedensratschlag)|publisher=Uni-kassel.de|access-date=24 July 2009|archive-date=23 September 2009|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090923155158/http://www.uni-kassel.de/fb5/frieden/themen/Theorie/kant.html|url-status=live}}</ref>
* 1797: ''[[Metaphysics of Morals]]'' ['''MM'''] (''Metaphysik der Sitten''). First part is The Doctrine of Right, which has often been published separately as The Science of Right.
* 1798: ''[[Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View]]'' ['''APPV'''] (''Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht'')
* 1798: ''Conflict of Faculties'' ['''CF''']<ref>{{cite web|url=http://chnm.gmu.edu/revolution/d/564/|title=Kant, The Contest of Faculties|year=1798|publisher=Chnm.gmu.edu|access-date=24 July 2009|archive-date=4 August 2011|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110804222523/http://chnm.gmu.edu/revolution/d/564/|url-status=live}}</ref> (''Der Streit der Fakultäten'')<ref>{{cite web|author=Immanuel Kant|url=http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/streit/streit.htm|title=Immanuel Kant: Der Streit der Facultäten – Kapitel 1|publisher=Projekt Gutenberg-DE|access-date=24 July 2009|language=de|archive-date=9 June 2007|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20070609150025/http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/kant/streit/streit.htm|url-status=live}}</ref>
* 1800: ''Logic'' (''Logik'')
* 1803: ''On Pedagogy'' (''Über Pädagogik'')<ref>Available [http://www.deutschestextarchiv.de/book/show/kant_paedagogik_1803 online at DeutschesTextArchiv.de] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160310102744/http://www.deutschestextarchiv.de/book/show/kant_paedagogik_1803 |date=10 March 2016 }}.</ref>
* 1804: ''Opus Postumum'' ['''OP''']
* 1817: ''Lectures on Philosophical Theology'' (''Immanuel Kants Vorlesungen über die philosophische Religionslehre'' edited by K.H.L. Pölitz) [The English edition of A.W. Wood & G.M. Clark (Cornell, 1978) is based on Pölitz' second edition, 1830, of these lectures.]{{efn|As noted by [[Allen W. Wood]] in his Introduction, p. 12. Wood further speculates that the lectures themselves were delivered in the Winter of 1783–84.}}
 
===Collected works in German===
[[Wilhelm Dilthey]] inaugurated the Academy edition (the ''Akademie-Ausgabe'' abbreviated as ''AA'' or ''Ak'') of Kant's writings (''Gesammelte Schriften'', [[Prussian Academy of Sciences|Königlich-Preußische Akademie der Wissenschaften]], Berlin, 1902–38) in 1895,<ref>Immanuel Kant, ''Notes and Fragments'', Cambridge University Press, 2005, p. xvi.</ref> and served as its first editor. The volumes are grouped into four sections:
* I. Kant's published writings (vols. 1–9),
* II. Kant's correspondence (vols. 10–13),
* III. Kant's literary remains, or ''[[Nachlass]]'' (vols. 14–23), and
* IV. Student notes from Kant's lectures (vols. 24–29).
 
An electronic version is also available: [https://web.archive.org/web/20190619210921/https://korpora.zim.uni-duisburg-essen.de/Kant/ ''Elektronische Edition der Gesammelten Werke Immanuel Kants''] (vols. 1–23).
 
==Notes==
{{notelist}}
 
==References==
===Citations===
{{reflist|22em}}
 
===Works cited===
{{refbegin|30em}}
* {{cite journal |last1=Bernasconi |first1=Robert |title=Defining Race Scientifically: A response to Michael Banton |journal=Ethnicities |date=2010 |volume=10 |issue=1 |pages=141–148 |doi=10.1177/14687968100100010802 |jstor=23890861 |s2cid=143925406 |issn=1468-7968}}
* {{cite web |last1=Bouie |first1=Jamelle |title=How the Enlightenment Created Modern Race Thinking and Why We Should Confront It |url=https://slate.com/news-and-politics/2018/06/taking-the-enlightenment-seriously-requires-talking-about-race.html |website=[[Slate (magazine)|Slate]] |access-date=15 June 2020 |language=en |date=5 June 2018 |archive-date=15 June 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200615090940/https://slate.com/news-and-politics/2018/06/taking-the-enlightenment-seriously-requires-talking-about-race.html |url-status=live }}
* {{cite web |title=Kant on the different human races (1777) |last=Bowersox |first=Jeff |url=https://blackcentraleurope.com/sources/1750-1850/kant-on-the-different-human-races-1777/ |website=Black Central Europe |access-date=16 June 2020 |language=en |date=4 February 2016 |archive-date=16 June 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200616003834/https://blackcentraleurope.com/sources/1750-1850/kant-on-the-different-human-races-1777/ |url-status=live }}
* {{Cite book |last=Caygill |first=Howard |year=1995 |title=A Kant Dictionary |publisher=Blackwell Publishing}}
* {{cite book |last1=Eze |first1=Emmanuel Chukwudi |title=Postcolonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader |year=1997a |publisher=Wiley |isbn=978-0631203391 |pages=103–131 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=BwkRtAEACAAJ |access-date=15 June 2020 |language=en |archive-date=20 December 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20201220055821/https://books.google.com/books?id=BwkRtAEACAAJ |url-status=live }}
* {{cite book |last1=Eze |first1=Emmanuel Chukwudi |title=Race and the Enlightenment: A Reader |year=1997b |publisher=Wiley |isbn=978-0631201366 |pages=39–48 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0BaguAEACAAJ |access-date=15 June 2020 |language=en |archive-date=20 December 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20201220055823/https://books.google.com/books?id=0BaguAEACAAJ |url-status=live }}
* {{cite book |title=Ethics: The Fundamentals |publisher=Blackwell |year=2007 |author=Driver, Julia |isbn=978-1405111546}}
* {{Cite book |last=di Giovanni |first=George |year=2005 |title=Freedom and Religion in Kant and His Immediate Successors |publisher=Cambridge University Press}}
* {{Cite book |last=Guyer |first=Paul |year=2014 |title=Kant |publisher=Routledge}}
* {{Cite book |last1=Guyer |first1=Paul |last2=Wood |first2=Alan W. |year=1998 |chapter=Introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason [Editors' Introduction] |title=The Critique of Pure Reason |publisher=Cambridge University Press}}
* {{cite encyclopedia |last=Jankowiak |first=Tim |year=2023 |title=Immanuel Kant |publisher=The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/kantview/ |access-date=4 March 2023}}
* {{cite encyclopedia |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-moral/#DutResForMorLaw |title=Kant's Moral Philosophy |encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |year=2008 |access-date=11 September 2013 |last=Johnson |first=Robert}}
* {{cite web |last1=Kant |first1=Immanuel |editor=Eze, Emmanuel Chukwudi|title=Kant on the Different Races of Man |year=2010|url=https://blogs.umass.edu/afroam391g-shabazz/files/2010/01/Kant-on-the-Different-Races-of-Man1.pdf |publisher=UMass Amherst |access-date=15 June 2020 |archive-date=1 August 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200801194450/https://blogs.umass.edu/afroam391g-shabazz/files/2010/01/Kant-on-the-Different-Races-of-Man1.pdf |url-status=live }}
* {{cite journal |last1=Kleingeld |first1=Pauline |title=Kant's Second Thoughts on Race |journal=The Philosophical Quarterly |date=October 2007 |volume=57 |issue=229 |pages=573–592 |doi=10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.498.x |hdl=11370/e15b6815-5eab-42d6-a789-24a2f6ecb946 |s2cid=55185762 |url=https://pure.rug.nl/ws/files/2768306/Kants_second_thoughts_on_race.pdf |access-date=14 December 2020 |archive-date=16 February 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190216193713/https://pure.rug.nl/ws/files/2768306/Kants_second_thoughts_on_race.pdf |url-status=live }}
* {{Cite book |last=Kuehn |first=Manfred |year=2001 |title=Kant: a Biography |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0521497046}}
* {{cite book |last1=Mills |first1=Charles W. |title=Black Rights/White Wrongs: The Critique of Racial Liberalism |year=2017 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0190245450 |pages=169–193 |doi=10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190245412.001.0001 |url=https://www.oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190245412.001.0001/acprof-9780190245412 |access-date=15 June 2020 |archive-date=16 June 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200616003829/https://www.oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190245412.001.0001/acprof-9780190245412 |url-status=live }}
* {{cite encyclopedia |last=Rohlf |first=Michael |year=2020 |title=Immanuel Kant |publisher=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 Edition) |editor=Edward N. Zalta |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/kant/}}
* {{Cite book |last=Schneewind |first=J. B. |year=2010 |chapter=Autonomy, Obligation, and Virtue: An Overview of Kant's Moral Philosophy |title=Essays on the History of Moral Philosophy |publisher=Oxford University Press}}
* {{cite news |last1=Shrage |first1=Laurie |title=Should we continue to teach thinkers like Kant, Voltaire and Hume without mention of the harmful prejudices they helped legitimize? |work=The New York Times |date=18 March 2019 |url=https://www.nytimes.com/2019/03/18/opinion/philosophy-anti-semitism.html |access-date=10 November 2022}}
* {{cite encyclopedia |last=Stang |first=Nicholas F. |year=2022 |title=Kant's Transcendental Idealism |publisher=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2022 Edition) |editor=Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2022/entries/kant-transcendental-idealism/}}
* {{Cite book |last=Wood |first=Allen |year=1999 |title=Kant's Ethical Thought |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0521648363}}
* {{Cite book |last=Wood |first=Allen |year=2006 |chapter=Kant's Practical Philosophy |title=The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism |editor=Karl Ameriks |publisher=Cambridge University Press. |isbn=978-0801486043}}
* {{Cite book |last=Wood |first=Allen |year=2008 |title=Kantian Ethics |publisher=Cambridge University Press. |isbn=978-0521671149}}
{{refend}}
 
==External links==
{{sister project links|d=Q9312|n=no|b=no|v=no|voy=no|m=no|mw=no|wikt=Kantian|s=Author:Immanuel_Kant|species=no}}
* {{Gutenberg author|id=1426|name=Immanuel Kant}}
* {{Internet Archive author|sname=Immanuel Kant}}
* {{Librivox author|id=1312}}
* [https://www.kantpapers.org KantPapers], authors and papers database powered by PhilPapers, focused on Kant, and located at Cornell University
* At the ''[[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]'':
** {{hlist | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/kantview/ Immanuel Kant: An Overview] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/kantaest/ Aesthetics] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/k-logic/ Logic] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/kantmeta/ Metaphysics] |
[https://www.iep.utm.edu/kantmind/ Philosophy of Mind] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/kant-rel/ Philosophy of Religion] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/rad-evil/ Radical Evil] | [https://www.iep.utm.edu/kant-transcendental-idealism/ Transcendental Idealism]}}
* At the ''[[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]'':
** {{hlist | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant/ Immanuel Kant] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-hume-causality/ Kant and Hume on Causality] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-hume-morality/ Kant and Hume on Morality] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-reason/ Kant's Account of Reason] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-aesthetics/ Kant's Aesthetics and Teleology] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-metaphysics/ Kant's Critique of Metaphysics] |
[https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-moral/ Kant's Moral Philosophy] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-development/ Kant's Philosophical Development] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-mathematics/ Kant's Philosophy of Mathematics] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-religion/ Kant's Philosophy of Religion] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-science/ Kant's Philosophy of Science] | [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-social-political/ Kant's Social and Political Philosophy] |
[https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-judgment/ Kant's Theory of Judgment] |
[https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-transcendental/ Kant's Transcendental Arguments] |
[https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-mind/ Kant's View of the Mind and Consciousness of Self] |
[https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-spacetime/ Kant's Views on Space and Time] |
[https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-conceptualism/ Kantian Conceptualism/Nonconceptualism] |
[https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-leibniz/ Leibniz's Influence on Kant]
}}
 
{{Navboxes
|title=Articles related to Immanuel Kant
|list=
{{Age of Enlightenment}}
{{metaphysics}}
{{epistemology}}
{{Social and political philosophy}}
{{Political philosophy}}
{{Ethics}}
{{philosophy of religion}}
{{aesthetics}}
{{jurisprudence}}
{{Liberalism}}
}}
{{Authority control}}
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Kant, Immanuel}}
[[ar:إيمانويل كانت]]
[[astCategory:Immanuel Kant| ]]
[[Category:1724 births]]
[[bn:ইমানুয়েল কান্ট]]
[[Category:1804 deaths]]
[[be:Імануіл Кант]]
[[Category:18th-century anthropologists]]
[[bs:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:18th-century essayists]]
[[bg:Имануел Кант]]
[[Category:18th-century German male writers]]
[[ca:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:18th-century German philosophers]]
[[cs:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:18th-century German writers]]
[[da:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:18th-century Prussian people]]
[[de:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:19th-century German anthropologists]]
[[et:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:19th-century German essayists]]
[[el:Εμμάνουελ Καντ]]
[[Category:German male essayists]]
[[es:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:19th-century German male writers]]
[[eo:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:19th-century German non-fiction writers]]
[[eu:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:19th-century German philosophers]]
[[fa:امانوئل کانت]]
[[Category:19th-century Prussian people]]
[[fr:Emmanuel Kant]]
[[Category:19th-century social scientists]]
[[ga:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:Academic staff of the University of Königsberg]]
[[gl:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:Age of Enlightenment]]
[[ko:이마누엘 칸트]]
[[Category:Enlightenment philosophers]]
[[hr:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German epistemologists]]
[[io:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German agnostics]]
[[id:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German ethicists]]
[[ia:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German idealists]]
[[is:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German logicians]]
[[it:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German Lutherans]]
[[he:עמנואל קאנט]]
[[Category:German male non-fiction writers]]
[[jv:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German political philosophers]]
[[la:Immanuel Kantius]]
[[Category:Humor researchers]]
[[lv:Imanuels Kants]]
[[Category:Idealists]]
[[lt:Imanuelis Kantas]]
[[Category:Kantianism|*]]
[[li:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:Kantian philosophers|*]]
[[hu:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German lecturers]]
[[mk:Имануел Кант]]
[[Category:Logicians]]
[[nl:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:Members of the Prussian Academy of Sciences]]
[[ja:イマヌエル・カント]]
[[Category:Metaphilosophers]]
[[no:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:Natural philosophers]]
[[pl:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:Ontologists]]
[[pt:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:People of the Age of Enlightenment]]
[[ro:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German philosophers of art]]
[[ru:Кант, Иммануил]]
[[Category:German philosophers of culture]]
[[scn:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German philosophers of education]]
[[simple:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German philosophers of history]]
[[sk:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German philosophers of law]]
[[sl:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:Philosophers of literature]]
[[sr:Имануел Кант]]
[[Category:Philosophers of logic]]
[[sh:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German philosophers of mind]]
[[fi:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German philosophers of religion]]
[[sv:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German philosophers of science]]
[[th:อิมมานูเอิล คานท์]]
[[Category:Philosophers of social science]]
[[vi:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:Philosophers of war]]
[[tr:Immanuel Kant]]
[[Category:German philosophy writers]]
[[uk:Кант Іммануїл]]
[[Category:Political liberals (international relations)]]
[[zh:伊曼努尔·康德]]
[[Category:Theoretical historians]]
[[Category:University of Königsberg alumni]]
[[Category:Writers about religion and science]]
[[Category:Natural law ethicists]]