Content deleted Content added
→The resource interpretation: the vending machine illustration is classic (meaning iconic), not classical (meaning part of the reigning orthodoxy prior to all the intellectual revolutions of the 20th century) |
Copy editing |
||
Line 9:
===Syntax===
The language of ''classical linear logic'' (CLL) is defined inductively by the [[Backus–Naur form|BNF notation]]
Line 34 ⟶ 35:
|}
Here {{math|<VAR>p</VAR>}} and {{math|<VAR>p</VAR><sup>⊥</sup>}} range over [[Atomic formula|logical atoms]]. For reasons to be explained below, the [[Logical connective|connectives]] ⊗, ⅋, 1, and ⊥ are called ''multiplicatives'', the connectives &, ⊕, ⊤, and 0 are called ''additives'', and the connectives ! and ? are called ''exponentials''.
We can further employ the following terminology:▼
▲employ the following terminology:
{| class="wikitable"
|+
Line 73 ⟶ 70:
Binary connectives ⊗, ⊕, & and ⅋ are associative and commutative; 1 is the unit for ⊗, 0 is the unit for ⊕, ⊥ is the unit for ⅋ and ⊤ is the unit for &.
Every proposition {{math|<VAR>A</VAR>}} in CLL has a '''dual''' {{math|<VAR>A</VAR><sup>⊥</sup>}}, defined as follows:
{| border="1" cellpadding="5" cellspacing="0" style="margin:auto"
|-
Line 108 ⟶ 106:
| & ⊤ || ⅋ ⊥ || ?
|}
Observe that {{math|(-)<sup>⊥</sup>}} is an [[Involution (mathematics)|involution]], i.e., {{math|<VAR>A</VAR><sup>⊥⊥</sup> {{=}} <VAR>A</VAR>}} for all propositions. {{math|<VAR>A</VAR><sup>⊥</sup>}} is also called the ''linear negation'' of {{math|<VAR>A</VAR>}}.
The columns of the table suggest another way of classifying the connectives of linear logic, termed '''{{em|{{visible anchor|polarity}}}}''': the connectives negated in the left column (⊗, ⊕, 1, 0, !) are called ''positive'', while their duals on the right (⅋, &, ⊥, ⊤, ?) are called ''negative''; cf. table on the right.
==Sequent calculus presentation==
Line 120 ⟶ 119:
We now give [[Sequent calculus#Inference rules|inference rules]] describing how to build proofs of sequents.<ref>Girard (1987), p.22, Def.1.15</ref>
First, to formalize the fact that we do not care about the order of propositions inside a context, we add the structural rule of [[exchange rule|exchange]]:
{| style="margin:auto" border="0"
Line 132 ⟶ 130:
|}
Note that we do '''not''' add the structural rules of weakening and contraction, because we do care about the absence of propositions in a sequent, and the number of copies present.
Next we add ''initial sequents'' and ''cuts'':
{| style="margin:auto"
|-
Line 159 ⟶ 157:
|}
The cut rule can be seen as a way of composing proofs, and initial sequents serve as the [[identity element|units]] for composition. In a certain sense these rules are redundant: as we introduce additional rules for building proofs below, we will maintain the property that arbitrary initial sequents can be derived from atomic initial sequents, and that whenever a sequent is provable it can be given a cut-free proof.
Now, we explain the connectives by giving ''logical rules''. Typically in sequent calculus one gives both "right-rules" and "left-rules" for each connective, essentially describing two modes of reasoning about propositions involving that connective (e.g., verification and falsification).
In a one-sided presentation, one instead makes use of negation: the right-rules for a connective (say ⅋) effectively play the role of left-rules for its dual (⊗).
So, we should expect a certain [[Logical harmony|"harmony"]] between the rule(s) for a connective and the rule(s) for its dual.▼
▲between the rule(s) for a connective and the rule(s) for its dual.
===Multiplicatives===
The rules for multiplicative conjunction (⊗) and disjunction (⅋):
{| style="margin:auto"
|-
Line 195 ⟶ 192:
and for their units:
{| style="margin:auto"
|-
Line 218 ⟶ 216:
|}
Observe that the rules for multiplicative conjunction and disjunction are [[Admissible rule|admissible]] for plain ''conjunction'' and ''disjunction'' under a classical interpretation
(i.e., they are admissible rules in [[Sequent calculus#The system LK|LK]]).
Line 225 ⟶ 222:
The rules for additive conjunction (&) and disjunction (⊕) :
{| style="margin:auto"
|-
Line 257 ⟶ 255:
|}
|}
and for their units:
{| style="margin:auto"
|-
Line 273:
|}
Observe that the rules for additive conjunction and disjunction are again admissible under a classical interpretation.
But now we can explain the basis for the multiplicative/additive distinction in the rules for the two different versions of conjunction: for the multiplicative connective (⊗), the context of the conclusion ({{math|Γ, Δ}}) is split up between the premises, whereas for the additive case connective (&) the context of the conclusion ({{math|Γ}}) is carried whole into both premises.
===Exponentials===
The exponentials are used to give controlled access to weakening and contraction. Specifically, we add structural rules of weakening and contraction for ?'d propositions:<ref>Girard (1987), p.25-26, Def.1.21</ref>
{| style="margin:auto"
|-
Line 306 ⟶ 302:
|}
|}
and use the following logical rules:
{| style="margin:auto"
|-
Line 329 ⟶ 327:
|}
|}
One might observe that the rules for the exponentials follow a different pattern from the rules for the other connectives, resembling the inference rules governing modalities in sequent calculus formalisations of the [[normal modal logic]] S4, and that there is no longer such a clear symmetry between the duals ! and ?.
This situation is remedied in alternative presentations of CLL (e.g., the [[Logic of unity|LU]] presentation).
==Remarkable formulas==
Line 436 ⟶ 434:
Multiplicative disjunction {{math|(<VAR>A</VAR> ⅋ <VAR>B</VAR>)}} is more difficult to gloss in terms of the resource interpretation, although we can encode back into linear implication, either as {{math|<VAR>A</VAR><sup>⊥</sup> ⊸ <VAR>B</VAR>}} or {{math|<VAR>B</VAR><sup>⊥</sup> ⊸ <VAR>A</VAR>}}.
==
===
{{main|Proof net}}
Introduced by [[Jean-Yves Girard]], proof nets have been created to avoid the ''bureaucracy'', that is all the things that make two derivations different in the logical point of view, but not in a "moral" point of view.
Line 475 ⟶ 474:
The goal of proof nets is to make them identical by creating a graphical representation of them.
==
===
{{See also|Quantale}}
Line 504 ⟶ 503:
{{Portal|Philosophy}}
* [[Linear type system]], a [[substructural type system]]▼
* [[
▲* [[Proof net]]s
* [[Geometry of interaction]]▼
* [[Game semantics]]
▲* [[Geometry of interaction]]
* [[Intuitionistic logic]]
* [[
▲* [[Linear type system]], a [[substructural type system]]
* [[Logic of unity]] (LU)
* [[Ludics]]
* [[
* [[Uniqueness type]]
==References==
{{Reflist}}
==Further reading==
* Girard, Jean-Yves. ''[http://girard.perso.math.cnrs.fr/linear.pdf Linear logic]'', Theoretical Computer Science, Vol 50, no 1, pp. 1–102, 1987.
* Girard, Jean-Yves, Lafont, Yves, and Taylor, Paul. ''[https://web.archive.org/web/20160704202340/http://www.cs.man.ac.uk/~pt/stable/Proofs+Types.html Proofs and Types]''. Cambridge Press, 1989.
Line 535 ⟶ 536:
==External links==
* {{Commons category-inline}}
* [http://bach.istc.kobe-u.ac.jp/llprover/ A Linear Logic Prover (llprover)], available for use online, from: Naoyuki Tamura / Dept of CS / Kobe University / Japan
{{Non-classical logic}}
|