Content deleted Content added
m →Proof |
|||
Line 13:
Cantor's argument is elegant and remarkably simple. The complete proof is presented below, with detailed explanations to follow.
{{
By definition of cardinality, we have <math>\mathrm{card}(X) < \mathrm{card}(Y)</math> for any two sets <math>X</math> and <math>Y</math> if and only if there is an [[injective function]] but no [[Bijective Function|bijective function]] from <math>X</math> to {{nowrap|<math>Y</math>.}} It suffices to show that there is no surjection from <math>X</math> to <math>Y</math>. This is the heart of Cantor's theorem: there is no surjective function from any set <math>A</math> to its power set. To establish this, it is enough to show that no function ''f'' that maps elements in <math>A</math> to subsets of <math>A</math> can reach every possible subset, i.e., we just need to demonstrate the existence of a subset of <math>A</math> that is not equal to <math>f(x)</math> for any <math>x</math> ∈ <math>A</math>. (Recall that each <math>f(x)</math> is a subset of <math>A</math>.) Such a subset is given by the following construction, sometimes called the [[Cantor's diagonal argument|Cantor diagonal set]] of <math>f</math>:<ref name="Dasgupta2013">{{cite book|author=Abhijit Dasgupta|title=Set Theory: With an Introduction to Real Point Sets|year=2013|publisher=[[Springer Science & Business Media]]|isbn=978-1-4614-8854-5|pages=362–363}}</ref><ref name="Paulson1992">{{cite book|author=Lawrence Paulson|title=Set Theory as a Computational Logic |url=https://www.cl.cam.ac.uk/techreports/UCAM-CL-TR-271.pdf|year=1992|publisher=University of Cambridge Computer Laboratory|page=14}}</ref>
:<math>B=\{x\in A \
This means, by definition, that for all ''x'' ∈ ''A'', ''x'' ∈ ''B'' if and only if ''x'' ∉ ''f''(''x''). For all ''x'' the sets ''B'' and ''f''(''x'') cannot be the same because ''B'' was constructed from elements of ''A'' whose [[Image (mathematics)|images]] (under ''f'') did not include themselves. More specifically, consider any ''x'' ∈ ''A'', then either ''x'' ∈ ''f''(''x'') or ''x'' ∉ ''f''(''x''). In the former case, ''f''(''x'') cannot equal ''B'' because ''x'' ∈ ''f''(''x'') by assumption and ''x'' ∉ ''B'' by the construction of ''B''. In the latter case, ''f''(''x'') cannot equal ''B'' because ''x'' ∉ ''f''(''x'') by assumption and ''x'' ∈ ''B'' by the construction of ''B''.
Equivalently, and slightly more formally, we just proved that the existence of ξ ∈ ''A'' such that ''f''(ξ) = ''B'' implies the following [[contradiction]]:
:<math>\begin{aligned}
\xi\in B &\iff \xi\notin f(\xi) && \text{(by definition of }B\text{)}.
\end{aligned}</math> Therefore, by [[reductio ad absurdum]], the assumption must be false.<ref name="Priest2002"/> Thus there is no ξ ∈ ''A'' such that ''f''(ξ) = ''B''; in other words, ''B'' is not in the image of ''f'' and ''f'' does not map to every element of the power set of ''A'', i.e., ''f'' is not surjective.
|