Content deleted Content added
m Spelling/grammar/punctuation/typographical correction |
This "extension" exactly describes the Rogers fp theorem above, thus move it there. Also, adjusted some of the formulations |
||
Line 16:
Rogers describes the following result as "a simpler version" of Kleene's (second) recursion theorem.{{sfn|Rogers|1967|loc=§11.2}}
{{math theorem | name = Rogers's fixed-point theorem | math_statement = If <math>F</math> is a total computable function, it has a fixed point in the above sense.}}
This essentially means that if we apply an [[Effectiveness|effective]] transformation to programs (say, replace instructions such as successor, jump, remove lines), there will always be a program whose behaviour is not altered by the transformation. This theorem can therefore be interpreted in the following manner: “given any effective procedure to transform programs, there is always a program
=== Proof of the fixed-point theorem ===
Line 37 ⟶ 39:
The theorem can be proved from Rogers's theorem by letting <math>F(p)</math> be a function such that <math>\varphi_{F(p)}(y) = Q(p,y)</math> (a construction described by the [[Smn theorem|S-m-n theorem]]). One can then verify that a fixed-point of this <math>F</math> is an index <math>p</math> as required. The theorem is constructive in the sense that a fixed computable function maps an index for <math>Q</math> into the index <math>p</math>.
▲This theorem can therefore be interpreted in the following manner “given any effective procedure to transform programs, there is always a program such that, when modified by the procedure, it does exactly what it did before, or it's impossible to write a program that changes the extensional behaviour of all other programs”.
=== Comparison to Rogers's theorem ===
|