Content deleted Content added
m Reverted edits by Markov Odometer (talk) to last version by Magioladitis |
No edit summary |
||
Line 1:
In mathematics, '''Carmichael's totient function conjecture''' concerns the [[Multiplicity (mathematics)|multiplicity]] of values of [[Euler's totient function]] ''φ''(''n''), which counts the number of integers less than and [[coprime]] to ''n''. It states that, for every ''n'' there is at least one other integer ''m'' ≠ ''n'' such that ''φ''(''m'') = ''φ''(''n'').
[[Robert Daniel Carmichael|Robert Carmichael]] first stated this conjecture in 1907, but as a theorem rather than as a conjecture. However, his proof was faulty and in 1922 he retracted his claim and stated the conjecture as an [[open problem]].
==Examples==
The totient function ''φ''(''n'') is equal to 2 when ''n'' is one of the three values 3, 4, and 6. Thus, if we take any one of these three values as ''n'', then either of the other two values can be used as the ''m'' for which ''φ''(''m'') = ''φ''(''n'').
Similarly, the totient is equal to 4 when ''n'' is one of the four values 5, 8, 10, and 12, and it is equal to 6 when ''n'' is one of the four values 7, 9, 14, and 18. In each case, there is more than one value of ''n'' having the same value of ''φ''(''n'').
The conjecture states that this phenomenon of repeated values holds for every
{|class="wikitable"
|''n''
|numbers ''k'' such that ''φ''(''k'') = ''n'' {{OEIS|id=A032447}}
|number of such ''k''s {{OEIS|id=A014197}}
|-
Line 136:
==Lower bounds==
There are very high [[lower bound]]s for Carmichael's conjecture that are relatively easy to determine. Carmichael himself proved that any counterexample to his conjecture (that is, a value ''n'' such that φ(''n'') is different from the totients of all other numbers) must be at least 10<sup>37</sup>, and [[Victor Klee]] extended this result to 10<sup>400</sup>. A lower bound of <math>10^{10^7}</math>was given by Schlafly and Wagon, and a lower bound of <math>10^{10^{10}}</math> was determined by Kevin Ford in 1998.<ref name=HBII228>Sándor & Crstici (2004) p. 228</ref>
The computational technique underlying these lower bounds depends on some key results of Klee that make it possible to show that the smallest counterexample must be divisible by squares of the primes dividing its totient value. Klee's results imply that 8 and Fermat primes (primes of the form 2<sup>''k''</sup> + 1) excluding 3 do not divide the smallest counterexample. Consequently, proving the conjecture is equivalent to proving that the conjecture holds for all integers congruent to
==Other results==
Ford also proved that if there exists a counterexample to the Conjecture, then a positive fraction (that is infinitely many) of the integers are likewise counterexamples.<ref name=HBII228/>
Although the conjecture is widely believed, [[Carl Pomerance]] gave a sufficient condition for an integer ''n'' to be a counterexample to the conjecture {{harv|Pomerance|1974}}. According to this condition, ''n'' is a counterexample if for every prime ''p'' such that ''p'' − 1 divides ''φ''(''n''), ''p''<sup>2</sup> divides
Another way of stating Carmichael's conjecture is that, if
''A''(''f'') denotes the number of positive integers ''n'' for which ''φ''(''n'') = ''f'', then ''A''(''f'') can never equal
==Notes==
|