Cantor's intersection theorem

This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Lim Wei Quan (talk | contribs) at 01:53, 23 September 2013 (Corrected minor error). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

In real analysis, a branch of mathematics, Cantor's intersection theorem, named after Georg Cantor, gives conditions under which an infinite intersection of nested, non-empty, sets is non-empty.

Theorem 1: If is a non-trivial, complete, metric space and is an infinite sequence of non-empty, closed sets such that and . Then, there exists an such that [1].

Theorem 2: If is a compact space and is an infinite sequence of non-empty, closed sets such that , then .

Notice the differences and the similarities between the two theorem. In Theorem 2, the are only assumed to be closed (and not compact, which is stronger) since given a compact space and a closed subset, is necessarily compact. Also, in Theorem 1 the intersection is exactly 1 point, while in Theorem 2 it could contain many more points. Interestingly, a metric space having the Cantor Intersection property (i.e. the theorem above holds) is necessarily complete (for justification see below). An example of an application of this theorem is the existence of limit points for self-similar contracting fractals[2].

Notice that each of the hypotheses above is essential. If the metric space were not complete, then one could construct a nested sequence of non-empty, compact sets converging to a "hole" in the space, i.e. with the usual metric and the sequence of sets, . If the sets are not closed, then one can construct sequences of nested sets which have empty intersection, i.e. with the collection, or the collection . This last case also demonstrates what can happen if the diameters are not tending to 0. However, another example would be and the infinite intersection will yield more than a single point.

Proof

Theorem 1: Suppose   is a non-trivial, complete metric space and   is an infinite family of non-empty closed sets in   such that   and  . Naturally we would like to use the completeness so we will construct a Cauchy sequence. Since each of the   is closed, there exists a   in the interior (i.e. positive distance to anything outside  ) of  . These   form a sequence. Since  , then given any positive real value,  , there exists a large   such that whenever  ,  . Since,  , then given any  ,   and therefore,  . Thus, the   form a Cauchy sequence. By the completeness of   there is a point   such that  . By the closure of each   and since   is in   for all  ,  . To see that   is alone in   assume otherwise. Take   and then consider the distance between   and   this is some value greater than 0 and implies that the  . Contradiction! Thus,   is very, very lonely in his small spartan little dorm room that is the infinite intersection of a sequence of closed set in a metric space that is complete, but how would he ever know.

Theorem 2: Suppose   is a compact topological space and   is an infinite sequence of non-empty, closed sets such that  . Assume, by contradiction, that  . Then we will build an open cover of   by considering the compliment of   in  , i.e.  . Each   is open since the   are closed. Notice that  , but we assumed that   so that means  . So, there are infinite many   covering our compact  . That means there exists a large   such that  . Notice, however, that   implies that   since I am throwing out less and less stuff each time. The only way for the nested and increasing   to cover   is if there is some index, call it  , such that  . This implies though that  . This is a contradiction since we assumed that the   were non-empty. Hence,  .

Notice that in regards to the proof of Theorem 2, we don't need Hausdorffness. At no point in time do we appeal to the nature of points in the space. It is simply a statement about empty or not.

Consider now a metric space   (not necessarily complete) in which   whenever   is an infinite sequence of non-empty, closed sets such that   and  . Now, let   be a Cauchy sequence in   and take  . The bar over the set means that we are taking the closure of the set under it. This guarantees that we are working with closed sets and since they contain the elements of our Cauchy sequence, we know them to be non-empty. In addition,   and since   such that when  , (note this hold for all indices larger than our large  ) then  . Hence,   satisfies the conditions above and there exists an   such that  . So,   is in the closure of all of the   and any open ball around   has non-empty intersection with the  . Now we will build a sub-sequence of the  , call it  , where  . This implies that   and since   was Cauchy then it too must converge to  . Since   was an arbitrary Cauchy sequence,   is complete.

References

  1. ^ "Real Analysis," H.L. Royden, P.M. Fitzpatrick, 4th edition, 2010, page 195
  2. ^ Ergodic Theory and Symbolic Dynamics in Hyperbolic Spaces, T. Bedford, M. Keane and C. Series eds., Oxford Univ. Press 1991, page 225
  • Weisstein, Eric W. "Cantor's Intersection Theorem". MathWorld.
  • Jonathan Lewin. An interactive introduction to mathematical analysis. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-01718-1. Section 7.8.