The statement
In set theory, Cantor's theorem states that the set of all subsets of any set A has a strictly greater cardinality than that of A. In particular, the set of all subsets of a countably infinite set is uncountably infinite.
The proof
The proof is a quick diagonal argument. Let f be any one-to-one function from A into the set of all subsets of A. It must be shown that f is necessarily not surjective. To do that, it is enough to exhibit a subset of A that is not in the image of f. That subset is
To show that B is not in the image of f, suppose that B is in the image of f. Then for some y in A, we have f(y) = B. Now consider whether y ε B or not. If y ε B, then y ε f(y), but that implies, by definition of B, that y not ε B. On the other hand if it is y not ε B, then y not ε f(y) and therefore y ε B. Either way, we get a contradiction.
Consequences
Most mathematicians are aware that the Hebrew letter (aleph) with various subscripts represents various infinite cardinal numbers, but fewer are aware that the second Hebrew letter (beth) also occurs. Let
be the cardinality of countably infinite sets; for concreteness, take the set N of natural numbers to be the typical case. Denote by P(A) the power set of A, i.e., the set of all subsets of A. Then define
so that
are respectively the cardinalities of
Each set in this sequence has cardinality strictly greater than every set preceding it.
More generally, for limit ordinals κ, we define
If we assume the axiom of choice, then infinite cardinalities are linearly ordered; no two cardinalities can fail to be comparable, and so, since no infinite cardinalities are between and , the celebrated continuum hypothesis can be stated in this notation by saying
The generalized continuum hypothesis" says the sequence of "beth numbers" thus defined is the same as the sequence of aleph numbers.