This is an old revision of this page, as edited by 132.64.140.68(talk) at 22:15, 22 September 2013(Attempting typesetting). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.Revision as of 22:15, 22 September 2013 by 132.64.140.68(talk)(Attempting typesetting)
In real analysis, a branch of mathematics, Cantor's intersection theorem, named after Georg Cantor, gives conditions under which an infinite intersection of nested, non-empty, sets is non-empty.
Theorem 1: If is a non-trivial, complete, metric space and is an infinite sequence of non-empty, closed sets such that and . Then, there exists an such that [1].
Theorem 2: If is a compact space and is an infinite sequence of non-empty, closed sets such that , then .
Notice the differences and the similarities between the two theorem. In Theorem 2, the are only required to be closed since given a compact space and a closed subset, then is necessarily compact. Also, in Theorem 1 the intersection is exactly 1 point, while in Theorem 2 it could contain many more points. Interestingly, a metric space can only have the Cantor Intersection property (i.e. the theorem above holds) if it is complete (for justification see below). An example of an application of this theorem is the existence of limit points for self-similar contracting fractals[2].
Notice that each of the hypotheses above is essential. If the metric space were not complete, then one could construct a nested sequence of non-empty, compact sets converging to a "hole" in the space, i.e. with the usual metric and the sequence of sets, . If the sets are not closed, then one can construct sequences of nested sets which have empty intersection, i.e. with the collection, or the collection . This last case also demonstrates what can happen if the diameters are not tending to 0. However, another example would be and the infinite intersection will yield more than a single point. Violation of the remaining hypotheses are clear and left to the reader as an exercise (I have always wanted to write that).
Proof
Theorem 1:
Suppose is a non-trivial, complete metric space and is an infinite family of non-empty closed sets in such that and . Naturally we would like to use the completeness so we will construct a Cauchy sequence. Since each of the is closed, there exists a in the interior (i.e. positive distance to anything outside ) of . These form a sequence. Since , then given any positive real value, , there exists a large such that whenever , . Since, , then given any , and therefore, . Thus, the form a Cauchy sequence. By the completeness of there is a point such that . By the closure of each and since is in for all , . To see that is alone in assume otherwise. Take and then consider the distance between and this is some value greater than 0 and implies that the . Contradiction! Thus, is very, very lonely in his small spartan little dorm room that is the infinite intersection of a sequence of closed set in a metric space that is complete, but how would he ever know.
Theorem 2:
Suppose is a compact topological space and is an infinite sequence of non-empty, closed sets such that . Assume, by contradiction, that . Then we will build an open cover of by considering the compliment of in , i.e. . Each is open since the are closed. Notice that , but we assumed that so that means . So, there are infinite many covering our compact . That means there exists a large such that . Notice, however, that implies that since I am throwing out less and less stuff each time. The only way for the nested and increasing to cover is if there is some index, call it , such that . This implies though that . This is a contradiction since we assumed that the were non-empty. Hence, .
Notice that in regards to the proof of Theorem 2, we don't need Hausdorffness. At no point in time do we appeal to the nature of points in the space. It is simply a statement about empty or not.
Consider now a metric space (not necessarily complete) in which whenever is an infinite sequence of non-empty, closed sets such that and . Now, let be a Cauchy sequence in and take . The bar over the set means that we are taking the closure of the set under it. This guarantees that we are working with closed sets and since they contain the elements of our Cauchy sequence, we know them to be non-empty. In addition, and since such that when , (note this hold for all indices larger than our large ) then . Hence, satisfies the conditions above and there exists an such that . So, is in the closure of all of the and any open ball around has non-empty intersection with the . Now we will build a sub-sequence of the , call it , where . This implies that and since was Cauchy then it too must converge to . Since was an arbitrary Cauchy sequence, is complete.