In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the beth numbers form a certain (unset) sequence of infinite cardinal numbers (also known as transfinite numbers), conventionally written , where is the Hebrew letter beth. The beth numbers are related to the aleph numbers (), but unless the generalized continuum hypothesis is true, there are numbers indexed by that are not indexed by or the gimel function . On the other hand, beth numbers are cofinal (Every cardinal number is less than a beth number.) in plain Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory.
Definition
editBeth numbers are indexed by ordinal numbers and defined in terms of the cumulative hierarchy by , where is the cardinality of and is the first infinite ordinal number. In particular, , and it follows by Cantor's theorem and transfinite induction that the sequence of beth numbers is strictly increasing. ( is the cardinality of the set of functions from to , so is the cardinality of the power set of .)
. In general, for ordinal , and for every limit ordinal . The axiom of choice implies that the inequality holds in general.
The second beth number is equal to , the cardinality of the continuum (the cardinality of the set of the real numbers), and the third beth number is the cardinality of the power set of the continuum.
Like aleph numbers, beth numbers are idempotent: . This follows by transfinite induction from two points:
- for every limit ordinal ; and
- for every idempotent cardinal number .
The axiom of choice implies that every set of cardinal numbers has a supremum and that for any set , the union set of all its members can be no larger than the supremum of its member cardinalities times its own cardinality. It follows (given the axiom) that for every limit ordinal .
Note that this behavior is different from that of successor ordinals. Even with the axiom of choice, cardinalities less than but greater than can exist. (In that case, the existence is undecidable in ZFC and controlled by the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis.)
Relation to the aleph numbers
editEven with the axiom of choice (provided Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory is consistent), little more is knowable about the relationship to aleph numbers than is stated above. For example, cannot be , but there is a model in which .
Assuming the axiom of choice, infinite cardinalities are linearly ordered; no two cardinalities can fail to be comparable. Since , the axiom implies that for all ordinals .
Given the axiom of choice, the continuum hypothesis is equivalent to
Given the axiom of choice, the generalized continuum hypothesis says the sequence of beth numbers is the same as the sequence of aleph numbers, i.e., for all ordinals . On the other hand, this assertion implies the axiom of choice since beth numbers are cofinal. (In Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, for some , so . It follows from the statement that , whence admits a well ordering.) An assertion closer to Cantor's original concern (about subsets of ) is that for every ordinal number and every cardinal number . These assertions are equivalent given the axiom of choice, but the second may be strictly weaker in plain Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory.
Specific cardinals
editBeth null
editSince (as noted above) this is equal to , or aleph null, sets with cardinality include:
- the natural numbers
- the rational numbers
- the algebraic numbers
- the computable numbers and computable sets
- the set of finite sets of integers or of rationals or of algebraic numbers
- the set of finite multisets of integers
- the set of finite sequences of integers.
Beth one
editSets with cardinality include:
- the transcendental numbers
- the irrational numbers
- the real numbers
- the complex numbers
- the uncomputable real numbers
- Euclidean space
- the power set of the natural numbers (the set of all subsets of the natural numbers)
- the set of sequences of integers (i.e., , which includes all functions from to )
- the set of sequences of real numbers,
- the set of all real analytic functions from to
- the set of all continuous functions from to
- the set of all functions from to with at most countable discontinuities [1]
- the set of finite subsets of real numbers
- the set of all analytic functions from to (the holomorphic functions)
- the set of all functions from the natural numbers to the natural numbers ( ).
Beth two
edit(pronounced beth two) is also referred to as (pronounced two to the power of ).
Sets with cardinality include:
- the power set of the set of real numbers, so it is the number of subsets of the real line, or the number of sets of real numbers
- the power set of the power set of the set of natural numbers
- the set of all functions from to ( )
- the set of all functions from to
- the set of all functions from to with uncountably many discontinuities [1]
- the power set of the set of all functions from the set of natural numbers to itself, or the number of sets of sequences of natural numbers
- the Stone–Čech compactifications of , , and
- the set of deterministic fractals in [2]
- the set of random fractals in .[3]
Beth omega
edit(pronounced beth omega) is the smallest uncountable strong limit cardinal.
Generalization
editThe more general symbol , for ordinals and cardinals , is occasionally used. Given the axiom of choice, it is defined by:
- if λ is a limit ordinal.
Without the axiom of choice, the definition is more complicated. The main difficulty is that the cardinalities of infinite disjoint unions cannot be calculated just from the cardinalities of the components. Still using recursion, define as follows:
- if λ is a limit ordinal.
Given an injection , we can construct recursively injections . If is a bijection then so is , so we can define the mapping for cardinal numbers by .
It follows (easily with the axiom of choice or after more meticulous argument otherwise) that
where is an ordinary beth number, and
In particular, . For any cardinal and any ordinal number , . On the other hand, for some , and it follows that for large (e.g. the ordinality of copies of stacked linearly). Thus for every cardinal number there is an ordinal number such that
- for every ordinal number .
This also holds in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with ur-elements (with or without the axiom of choice), provided that the ur-elements form a set which is equinumerous with a pure set (a set whose transitive closure contains no ur-elements). If the axiom of choice holds, then any set of ur-elements is equinumerous with a pure set. (If is not equinumerous with any pure set then it is not clear what object of set theory would be its cardinality, let alone . However, we can still construct as above, and if is equinumerous with then is equinumerous with .)
Borel determinacy
editBorel determinacy is implied by the existence of all beths of countable index.[4]
See also
editReferences
edit- ^ a b Soltanifar, Mohsen (2023). "A classification of elements of function space F(R,R)". Mathematics. 11 (17): 3715. arXiv:2308.06297. doi:10.3390/math11173715.
- ^ Soltanifar, Mohsen (2021). "A generalization of the Hausdorff dimension theorem for deterministic fractals". Mathematics. 9 (13): 1546. arXiv:2007.07991. doi:10.3390/math9131546.
- ^ Soltanifar, Mohsen (2022). "The second generalization of the Hausdorff dimension theorem for random fractals". Mathematics. 10 (5): 706. arXiv:2109.02739. doi:10.3390/math10050706. hdl:1807/110291.
- ^ Leinster, Tom (23 July 2021). "Borel Determinacy Does Not Require Replacement". The n-Category Café. The University of Texas at Austin. Retrieved 25 August 2021.
Bibliography
edit- T. E. Forster, Set Theory with a Universal Set: Exploring an Untyped Universe, Oxford University Press, 1995 — Beth number is defined on page 5.
- Bell, John Lane; Slomson, Alan B. (2006) [1969]. Models and Ultraproducts: An Introduction (reprint of 1974 ed.). Dover Publications. ISBN 0-486-44979-3. See pages 6 and 204–205 for beth numbers.
- Roitman, Judith (2011). Introduction to Modern Set Theory. Virginia Commonwealth University. ISBN 978-0-9824062-4-3. See page 109 for beth numbers.