Anscombe-Aumann subjective expected utility model

In decision theory, the Anscombe-Aumann subjective expected utility model (also known as Anscombe-Aumann framework, Anscombe-Aumann approach, or Anscombe-Aumann representation theorem) is a framework to formalizing subjective expected utility (SEU) developed by Frank Anscombe and Robert Aumann.[1]

Anscombe and Aumann's approach can be seen as an extension of Savage's framework to deal with more general acts, leading to a simplification of Savage's representation theorem. It can also be described as a middle-course theory that deals with both objective uncertainty (as in the von Neumann-Morgenstern framework) and subjective uncertainty (as in Savage's framework).[2]

The Anscombe-Aumann framework builds upon previous work by Savage,[3] von Neumann, and Morgenstern[4] on the theory of choice under uncertainty and the formalization of SEU. It has since become one of the standard approaches to choice under uncertainty, serving as the basis for alternative models of decision theory such as maxmin expected utility, multiplier preferences and choquet expected utility.[5]

Setup

edit

Roulette lotteries and horse lotteries

edit

The Anscombe-Aumann framework is essentially the same as Savage's, dealing with primitives  . The only difference is that now the set of acts   consists of functions  , where   is the set of lotteries over outcomes  .

This way, Anscombe and Aumann differentiate between the subjective uncertainty over the states   (referred to as a horse lottery), and the objective uncertainty given by the acts   (referred to as roulette lotteries).

Importantly, such assumption greatly simplifies the proof of an expected utility representation, since it gives the set   a linear structure inherited from  . In particular, we can define a mixing operation: given any two acts   and  , we have the act   define by

 

for all  .

Expected utility representation

edit

As in Savage's model, we want to derive conditions on the primitives   such that the preference   can be represented by expected-utility maximization. Since acts are now themselves lotteries, however, such representation involves a probability distribution   and a utility function   which must satisfy

 

Axioms

edit

Anscombe and Aumann posit the following axioms regarding  :

  • Axiom 1 (Preference relation) :   is complete (for all  , it's true that   or  ) and transitive.
  • Axiom 2 (Independence axiom): given  , we have that
 

for any   and  .

  • Axiom 3 (Archimedean axiom): for any   such that  , there exist   such that
 

For any act   and state  , let   be the constant act with value  .

  • Axiom 4 (Monotonicity): given acts  , we have
 
  • Axiom 5 (Non-triviality): there exist acts   such that  .

Anscombe-Aumann representation theorem

edit

Theorem: given an environment  , the preference relation   satisfies Axioms 1-5 if and only if there exist a probability distribution   and a non-constant utility function   such that

 

for all acts  . Furthermore,   is unique and   is unique up to positive affine transformations.[1][5]

See also

edit

Notes

edit

References

edit
  1. ^ a b Anscombe, Frank; Aumann, Robert (1963). "A Definition of Subjective Probability". Annals of Mathematical Statistics. 34 (1): 199–205. doi:10.1214/aoms/1177704255.
  2. ^ Kreps, David (1988). Notes on the Theory of Choice. Westview Press. ISBN 978-0813375533.
  3. ^ Savage, Leonard J. (1954). The Foundations of Statistics. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
  4. ^ von Neumann, John; Morgenstern, Oskar (1944). Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0691130613. {{cite book}}: ISBN / Date incompatibility (help)
  5. ^ a b Gilboa, Itzhak (2009). Theory of Decision under Uncertainty. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521741231.