Background

edit

Discovery

edit

The fundamental theorem of calculus relates to differentiation and integration, showing that these operations are essentially inverses of one another. Before the discovery of this theorem, it was not recognized that these two operations were related. Ancient Greek mathematicians knew how to compute area via infinitesimals, an operation that is nowadays called integration.[1] The origins of differentiation likewise predate the fundamental theorem of calculus by hundreds of years; for example, in the fourteenth century the notions of continuity of functions and motion were studied by the Oxford Calculators and other scholars. The historical relevance of the fundamental theorem of calculus is not the ability to calculate these operations, but the realization that the two seemingly distinct operations (calculation of geometric areas, and calculation of gradients) are closely related.

From the conjecture and the proof of the fundamental theorem of calculus, calculus as a unified theory of integration and differentiation is started. The first published statement and proof of a rudimentary form of the fundamental theorem strongly geometric was by James Gregory.[2] Isaac Barrow proved a more generalized version of the theorem.[3] His student Isaac Newton completed the development of the surrounding mathematical theory.[4][5] Gottfried Leibniz systematized the knowledge into a calculus for infinitesimal quantities and introduced the notation used today.[6]

Overview

edit

The derivative of a function with a single variable is a tool quantifying the sensitivity of change of a function's output concerning its input. When it exists, it can be considered as the tangent line's slope to the graph of the function at that point. Given that a function of a real variable   is differentiable in real ___domain, the derivative of a function   with respect to  , denoted as  , can be defined in terms of limit:[7]  

The integral is a continuous summation, used in calculating the area under a graph and the volume of a graph revolving around an axis. Such calculations are implemented whenever there are two points bounded in the real line called the interval exists,[a] and the integral is called the definite integral. This integral is defined by using Riemann sum: given that   differentiable at  , and partition of such interval   that can be expressed as  , then the definite integral can be defined as   where   represents the difference between two each   and   in the interval.[7]

First theorem

edit

Statement

edit

The first fundamental theorem of calculus describes the value of any function as the rate of change (the derivative) of its integral from a fixed starting point up to any chosen end point. It can be interpreted as an example that velocity is the function, and integrating it from the starting time up to any given time to obtain a distance function whose derivative is that velocity. The first fundamental theorem of calculus is stated formally as follows: let   be a continuous real-valued function defined on a closed interval  . For all   in that same closed interval, let   be the function defined as:[8]   Then   is continuous on   and differentiable on the open interval  , and   for all   in  , such that   is an antiderivative of  .[8]

Proof

edit

For a given function  , define the function   as   For any two numbers   and   in  , one has   The latter equality results from the basic properties of integrals and the additivity of areas. According to the mean value theorem for integration, there exists a real number   such that   It follows that  , and thus that   Taking the limit as   and keeping in mind that   one gets   that is,  , according to the definition of the derivative, the continuity of f, and the squeeze theorem.[9]

Second theorem

edit

Statement

edit

The second fundamental theorem says that the sum of infinitesimal changes in a quantity (the integral of the derivative of the quantity) adds up to the net change in the quantity. Formally, let   be a real-valued function on a closed interval   and   a continuous function on   which is an antiderivative of   in  :[10]   If   is Riemann integrable on  , then[10]  

Proof

edit

This is a limit proof by Riemann sums.

To begin, we recall the mean value theorem. Stated briefly, if F is continuous on the closed interval [a, b] and differentiable on the open interval (a, b), then there exists some c in (a, b) such that  

Let f be (Riemann) integrable on the interval [a, b], and let f admit an antiderivative F on (a, b) such that F is continuous on [a, b]. Begin with the quantity F(b) − F(a). Let there be numbers x0, ..., xn such that  

It follows that  

Now, we add each F(xi) along with its additive inverse, so that the resulting quantity is equal:  

The above quantity can be written as the following sum:

The function F is differentiable on the interval (a, b) and continuous on the closed interval [a, b]; therefore, it is also differentiable on each interval (xi−1, xi) and continuous on each interval [xi−1, xi]. According to the mean value theorem (above), for each i there exists a   in (xi−1, xi) such that  

Substituting the above into (1'), we get  

The assumption implies   Also,   can be expressed as   of partition  .

 
A converging sequence of Riemann sums. The number in the upper left is the total area of the blue rectangles. They converge to the definite integral of the function.

We are describing the area of a rectangle, with the width times the height, and we are adding the areas together. Each rectangle, by virtue of the mean value theorem, describes an approximation of the curve section it is drawn over. Also   need not be the same for all values of i, or in other words that the width of the rectangles can differ. What we have to do is approximate the curve with n rectangles. Now, as the size of the partitions get smaller and n increases, resulting in more partitions to cover the space, we get closer and closer to the actual area of the curve.

By taking the limit of the expression as the norm of the partitions approaches zero, we arrive at the Riemann integral. We know that this limit exists because f was assumed to be integrable. That is, we take the limit as the largest of the partitions approaches zero in size, so that all other partitions are smaller and the number of partitions approaches infinity.

So, we take the limit on both sides of (2'). This gives us  

Neither F(b) nor F(a) is dependent on  , so the limit on the left side remains F(b) − F(a).  

The expression on the right side of the equation defines the integral over f from a to b. Therefore, we obtain   which completes the proof.

Generalizations

edit

The function   does not have to be continuous over the whole interval. The first theorem may be applied in the case of Lebesgue integrable function. This concludes that the function   is differentiable almost everywhere and   almost everywhere. On the real line this statement is equivalent to Lebesgue's differentiation theorem. These results remain true for the Henstock–Kurzweil integral, which allows a larger class of integrable functions.[11] The Lebesgue integrable function   may also be applied in the second theorem, which has an antiderivative   but not all integrable functions do.[12] This result may fail for continuous functions   that admit a derivative   at almost every point  , as the example of the Cantor function shows. However, if   is absolutely continuous, it admits a derivative   at almost every point  , and moreover   is integrable, with   equal to the integral of   on [a, b]. Conversely, if   is any integrable function, then   as given in the first formula will be absolutely continuous with   almost everywhere. In higher dimensions, Lebesgue's differentiation theorem generalizes the Fundamental theorem of calculus by stating that for almost every  , the average value of a function   over a ball of radius   centered at   tends to   as   tends to 0.

The conditions of this theorem may again be relaxed by considering the integrals involved as Henstock–Kurzweil integrals. Specifically, if a continuous function   admits a derivative   at all but countably many points, then   is Henstock–Kurzweil integrable and   is equal to the integral of   on [a, b]. The difference here is that the integrability of   does not need to be assumed.[13]

There is a version of the theorem for complex functions: suppose   is an open set in   and   is a function that has a holomorphic antiderivative   on  . Then for every curve  , the curve integral can be computed as  

The fundamental theorem can be generalized to curve and surface integrals in higher dimensions and on manifolds. One such generalization offered by the calculus of moving surfaces is the time evolution of integrals. The most familiar extensions of the fundamental theorem of calculus in higher dimensions are the divergence theorem and the gradient theorem.

One of the most powerful generalizations in this direction is the generalized Stokes theorem (sometimes known as the fundamental theorem of multivariable calculus): Let   be an oriented piecewise smooth manifold of dimension   and let   be a smooth compactly supported  -form on  . If   denotes the boundary of   given its induced orientation, then   Here   is the exterior derivative, which is defined using the manifold structure only.[14] The theorem is often used in situations where   is an embedded oriented submanifold of some bigger manifold (e.g.   on which the form   is defined.

The fundamental theorem of calculus allows us to pose a definite integral as a first-order ordinary differential equation.   can be posed as   with   as the value of the integral.

Notes

edit
  1. ^ Two different intervals are the open interval and closed interval. An interval is said to be open if  , denoted as  . Conversely, an interval is said to be closed if  , dnoeted as  .

References

edit
  1. ^ Garding, Lars (1977). Encounter with Mathematics. Springer. p. 124.
  2. ^ Malet, Antoni (1993). "James Gregorie on tangents and the "Taylor" rule for series expansions". Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 46 (2). Springer-Verlag: 97–137. doi:10.1007/BF00375656. S2CID 120101519. Gregorie's thought, on the other hand, belongs to a conceptual framework strongly geometrical in character.
  3. ^ Child, James Mark; Barrow, Isaac (1916). The Geometrical Lectures of Isaac Barrow. Chicago: Open Court Publishing Company.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher ___location (link)
  4. ^ Roy, Ranjan (2021). Series and Products in the Development of Mathematics. Vol. I (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 190–191. ISBN 978-1-108-70945-3.
  5. ^ Błaszczyk, P.; Katz, M. G.; Sherry, D. (March 2013). "Ten misconceptions from the history of analysis and their debunking". Foundations of Science. 18 (1): 43–74. arXiv:1202.4153. doi:10.1007/s10699-012-9285-8. S2CID 119134151.
  6. ^ Varberg, Purcell & Rigdon 2007, p. 104.
  7. ^ a b Varberg, Dale E.; Purcell, Edwin J.; Rigdon, Steven E. (2007). Calculus (9th ed.). Pearson Prentice Hall. p. 232. ISBN 978-0131469686.
  8. ^ a b Varberg, Purcell & Rigdon (2007), p. 234–235.
  9. ^ Leithold, L. (1996). The calculus of a single variable (6th ed.). New York: HarperCollins College Publishers. p. 380.
  10. ^ a b Varberg, Purcell & Rigdon (2007), p. 243.
  11. ^ Bartle (2001), Thm. 4.11.
  12. ^ Rudin 1987, th. 7.21
  13. ^ Bartle (2001), Thm. 4.7.
  14. ^ Spivak, M. (1965). Calculus on Manifolds. New York: W. A. Benjamin. pp. 124–125. ISBN 978-0-8053-9021-6.